Liberalism and the Berlinian Paradox - Cevipof [PDF]

many “nietzschian” accounts of liberalism -‐ for instance as stated by the French philosopher Gerard. Lebrun ([1981] 200

0 downloads 5 Views 262KB Size

Recommend Stories


Liberalism and Democracy
Learning never exhausts the mind. Leonardo da Vinci

Between liberalism and democracy
Knock, And He'll open the door. Vanish, And He'll make you shine like the sun. Fall, And He'll raise

Kavelin and Russian Liberalism
The happiest people don't have the best of everything, they just make the best of everything. Anony

The challenge of liberalism
You're not going to master the rest of your life in one day. Just relax. Master the day. Than just keep

Adaptation and the Easterlin Paradox
Goodbyes are only for those who love with their eyes. Because for those who love with heart and soul

Liberalism and Religion
Stop acting so small. You are the universe in ecstatic motion. Rumi

Liberalism,Neoliberalism and the Global Public Good
How wonderful it is that nobody need wait a single moment before starting to improve the world. Anne

[PDF] Review The Paradox of Choice
Don't fear change. The surprise is the only way to new discoveries. Be playful! Gordana Biernat

White Liberalism
Ask yourself: Do I believe that everything is meant to be, or do I think that things just tend to happen

From Political Liberalism to Para-Liberalism
Stop acting so small. You are the universe in ecstatic motion. Rumi

Idea Transcript


1      

Liberalism  and  the  Berlinian  Paradox    (“Le  pluralism  libéral  et  sés  critiques”)       Lucas  Petroni*     University  of  São  Paulo  (Brazil)       [FIRST  DRAFT]         In   this   brief   speech   on   moral   pluralism   and   political   liberalism   I   would   like   to   address  the  famous  argument  advanced  by  Isaiah  Berlin  concerning  the  (inherent)  clash  of   values.  At  first  sight  seems  like  a  normative  argument  and  could  be  stated  in  one  phrase  by   Berlin’s   dictum:   “what   is   clear   is   that   values   can   clash   –   that   is   why   civilizations   are  

incompatible”  1.  It  is  true  (a  clear  truth  perhaps)  that  the  range  of  things  that  we,  as  human   beings,  give  value  are  vast  and  in  itself  contradictory.     One  way  to  characterize  the  main   goal  of  Berlin’s  philosophy   –  including  his  aesthetical  and  epistemological  efforts  –  is  his   persistence  in  arguing  for  a  “pluralistic”  worldview  in  which  many  conflicting  answers  for   the   same   problems   are   the   only   justification   offered   by   philosophy   that   we   can   expect.     Moral   pluralism   in   this   sense   should   be   contrasted   with   “monistic”   accounts   which   state   that  we  already  have–  or  we  will  have  in  the  long  run  –  one  correct  way  to  deal  with  our   normative   crucial   questions.   One   important   class   of   “illegitimated”   theorizing   by   these   criteria   would   be   recent   attempts   to   provide   our   societies   with   general   principles   of   justice  (political  or  socioeconomic  ones)  even  if  these  theories  are  taken  by  granted  moral   pluralism   and   political   liberalism2.   Under   this   argument   we   should   be   skeptics   about   “theories”  of  justice.                                                                                                                              

*

  M.A.   researcher   of   the   Faculty   of   Letters,   Philosophy   and   Human   Science   (USP).   I   would   like   to   acknowledge  the  Department  of  Political  Science  for  the  institutional  help  and  financial  support  to  this   work.       1    PL  p.  10.     2     It   is   worth   contrasting   Berlin’s   pluralism   with   the   pluralist   account   of   values   that   we   find   in   Max   Weber.   Both   depart   from   the   pluralism   of   values   to   argue   about   skepticism   when   it   comes   to   general   normative   principles,   and   both   authors   have   been   considered   the   forefathers   of   XX   century   liberal   theory.   Notwithstand   these   similarities,   Weber’s   work   bears   upon   a   “nietzschian”   flavor   that   is   completely  absent  in  Berlin’s.  As  I  shall  argue  value  incommensurability  to  Berlin  is  objective  –  so  it  is  an   objective   truth   -­‐   rather   than   caused   by   a   clash   of   subjective   perspectives   or   attachments   of   personal   commitments.  As  John  Rawls  once  said  “the  differences  between  Berlin’s  and  Weber’s  views  are  marked   […]  I  believe  that  Weber’s  view  rest  on  a  form  of  value  skepticism  and   voluntarism.  Political  tragedies   arises   from   the   conflict   of   subjective   commitments   and   resolute   wills”   (Rawls   2001   p.   155   fn.   29).     Roughly,   my   criticism   of   agonistic   foundations   of   liberalism   does   apply   also   to   Weber,   as   it   does   to    

1    

2     The  reasons  why  I  have  chosen  Berlin’s  argument  are  two:  First,  Berlin  has  shown   that   political   theory   could   not   drive   away   from   classical   problems   settled   by   political   philosophy   neither   could   we   avoid   the   stringent   problem   of   how   to   justify   political   decisions.  His  celebrated  defenses  of  political  theory,  especially  in  pieces  as  “Does  Political   Theory  Still  Exist?”  and  “Two  Concepts  of  Liberty”,  make  sense  only  when  framed  against   his  argument  of  moral  pluralism.  Since  then  this  concept  has  played  an  important  role  in   the  whole  field  of  practical  philosophy  and  its  influence  can  be  identified  in  the  works  of   Bernard   Williams,   John   Gray,   Michael   Walzer,   and   John   Rawls   (who   was   a   former   Berlin   student  in  Oxford).    In  several  important  ways  the  thought  of  Isaiah  Berlin  has  influenced   analytical  philosophy  for  decades  and  so  has  his  skeptical  challenges.   Despite   this   generalize   picture   of   Berlin’s   theory,   I   will   try   to   discuss   with   you   today   a   rather   modest   question:   does   this   kind   of   moral   skepticism   entailed   by   Berlin’s   argument  is  sound  all  the  way  down?  What  kind  of  political  liberalism  does  it  support?  My   first   aim   (1)   is   to   present   an   analysis   of   the   moral   pluralism   argument   looking   for   its   normative   elements-­‐   especially   what   is   entangled   by   it.   I   shall   call   it   agonistic  pluralism3   and   I   hope   that   this   label   can   help   us   to   identity   a   family   of   related   political   liberalisms   with   its   same   features.   I   intend   to   present   the   structure   of   Berlin’s   argument   of   moral   pluralism   through   two   basic   epistemic   premises:   a   principle   of   value   objectivity,   and   a   principle   of   value   incommensurability.   Together   they   enable   Berlin   to   criticize   the   rationalistic   grounds   of   western   moral   reasoning   by   exposing   the   “failure   of   the   utopian   projects”.  After  that  (2),  I  will  try  to  build  the  argument  by  trying  to  access  the  conceptual   soundness  of  agonistic  pluralism.    Specifically,  I  would  like  to  expose  a  paradox  (or  at  least   a  serious  inconclusiveness)  between  its  epistemic  premises  and  its  normative  conclusions.   Does   moral   pluralism,   even   in   its   “agonistic”   account,   could   cut   off   general   principles   of   justice?   It   brings   up   two   related   problems   concerning   the   concept   and   the   practice   of   tolerance.  Finally  (3)  I  would  like  to  discuss  the  recent  attempts  to  build  liberal  theory  on   agonistic  bases  through  the  works  of  John  Gray  and  Richard  Rorty.  Despite  their  political   and   theoretical   divergences   both   represent   one   important   branch   of   political   liberalism   option  today.  In  fact  we  could  classify  different  political  liberalism  due  to  the  place  moral   pluralism   occupy   into   the   theory.   I   would   like   to   conclude   my   presentation   addressing   a   rival  concept  of  political  liberalism  found  in  egalitarian  standards.  Authors  as  John  Rawls,   Thomas  Nagel  and  Thomas  Scanlon  have  showed  us  a    new  and  interesting  way  to  match                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                               many   “nietzschian”   accounts   of   liberalism   -­‐   for   instance   as   stated   by   the   French   philosopher   Gerard   Lebrun  ([1981]  2001).   3  The  name  comes  from  Gray  1993  (a).  The  first  section  of  my  paper  relies  on  Gray’s  studies  on  Berlin.   However,   I   do   not   share   Gray’s   conclusions   extract   from   this   interpretation   –   as   discussed   in   section   (2).   The   main   reason   for   rejecting   Gray’s   conclusions   is   the   same   one   against   the   impossibility   of   any   kind   of   moral  theory  or  general  conception  of  justice.  

2    

3     the   moral   pluralism   assumptions   with   the   claims   of   social   justice   giving   a   egalitarian   foundation  to  the  principle  of  toleration.    

1.    The  structure  of  agonistic  pluralism       The  core  of  Isaiah  Berlin’s  philosophy  rests  on  the  idea  that  a  philosophia  perennis  

 

is  impossible  because  not  every  value  are  necessarily  compatible  with  each  other  (DU  p.8).   The   conception   that   human   values   are   true   and   many   –   and   because   of   that   -­‐   they   clash   against   each   other   has   been   called   agonistic   pluralism4.   As   Berlin   famously   summarizes   this  view:     the   notion   of   a   perfect   whole,   the   ultimate   solution,   in   which   all   good   things   coexist,   seems   to   me   to   be   not   merely   unattainable   –   that   is   a   truism  –  but  conceptually  incoherent;  I  do  not  know  what  is  meant  by  a   harmony  of  this  kind.  Some  among  the  Great  Goods  cannot  live  together.   That  is  a  conceptual  truth.  We  are  doomed  to  choose,  and  every  choice   may   entail   an   irreparable   loss.   Happy   are   those   who   live   under   a   discipline   which   they   accept   without   question,   who   freely   obey   the   orders   of   the   leaders,   spiritual   or   temporal,   whose   word   is   fully     accepted  as  unbreakable  law;  or  those  who  have,  by  their  own  methods,   arrived  at  clear  and  unshakable  convictions  about  what  to  do  and  what   to  be  that  brook  no  possible  doubt.  I  can  only  say  that  those  who  rest  on   such   comfortable   beds   of   dogma   are   victims   of   forms   of   self-­‐induced   myopia,   blinkers   that   may   make   for   contentment,   but   not   for   understanding  of  what  it  is  to  be  human  (PI  p.  11).       For  this  paper  purposes  I  will  define  agonistic  pluralism  as  an  argument  in  which  there  are  

a  finite  set  of  objective  values,  i.  e.  capable  of  being  recognized  as  such  for  everyone,  even   though   they   are   incommensurable   among   them.     To   understand   Berlin’s   argument   we   should  pay  attention  to  at  least  two  main  premises.  The  first  one  is  the  principle  of  value   objectivity.  The  second  one  is  the  principle  of  value  incommensurability.  To  state  each  of   them   separately   is   crucial   to   evaluate   both   the   argument’s   cogency   and   its   practical   implications.    I  think  that  these  two  premises  can  give  us  support  to  understand  Berlin’s   proposition   that   we   are   doomed   to   choose   and   every   choice   may   entails   an   irreparable   loss.     (a)  Objectivity    

                                                                                                                        4

   Gray  1993(a).    

 

3    

4      

True  values  are  objectivity-­‐bearers.  “There  is  a  world  of  objective  values.  By  this  I  

mean   those   ends   that   men   pursue   fake   for   their   own   sake,   to   which   other   things   are   means”   (PI   p.9).   Contrasting   with   this   picture   of   moral   world   we   could   think   on,   for   instance,   “emotivism”   for   which   moral   decisions   are   made,   in   the   end,   by   subjective   preferences  or  volitions.  “Ought-­‐sentences”  would  be  a  matter  of  personal,  or  cultural,  or   historical,   taste.   This   kind   of   theory   in   Berlin’s   account   would   be   just   a   sophisticated   version   of   relativism5.   In   fact   the   ingenuity   of   agonistic   pluralism   relies   upon   the   dissociation   between   skepticism   and   subjectivism.   Take   for   instance   the   argument   of   “moral  diversity”  as  stated  by  John  Mackie:  it  is  such  a  plain  fact  that  people  disagree  so   hard   about   morality   (even   within   closed   social   groups)   that   we   could   hardly   expect   that   moral  claims  would  have  an  “objective”  source6.  Rather,  if  moral  agents  need  to  grasp  true   values,  or  if  they  need  to  choose  between  them,  it  is  because  they  are  coercive  upon  their   lives   values.   Given   that   nobody   can   “make   them   up”   we   can   say   that   in   one   important   sense   they   exist   independently   of   individual   intentionality.   Furthermore,   it   means   that   agonistic  pluralism  must  be  distinguished  from  “vulgar”  kinds  of  relativism  because  Berlin   knows   exactly   how   inconsistent   conceptual   relativism   is.   Take   for   instance   Bernard   Williams’   characterization   of   cultural   relativism7.     It   is   made   of   two   contradictory   propositions:  (i)  something  is  right,  or  is  valued  by  S,  where  S  is  a  particular  society,  and   (ii)  it  is  wrong,  or  should  not  be  valued  to  judge  or  to  interfere  in  local  believes.  Note  that   while   (i)   is   a   relative   proposition,   (ii)   is   universal.   Even   if   values   are   culture-­‐specific   the   principle  of  culture  toleration  is  not.      

The   main   reason   why   Berlin   avoid   (and   argue   against)   moral   relativism   rests   on  

his   methodological   commitment   to   interpretation   as   a   way   to   achieve   knowledge.   “Members   of   one   culture   can,   by   the   force   of   imaginative   insight,   understand   […]   the   values,  the  ideals,  the  forms  of  life  of  another  culture  or  society,  even  those  remote  in  time   or   space.   Even   though   sometimes   different   cultures   could   see   one   another   as   unacceptable,  “they  can  grasp  how  one  might  be  a  full  human  being,  with  whom  one  can   communicate”  (PI  p.9).  The  legitimacy  of  interpretation  as  a  method  for  human  knowledge   will   be   shared   by   authors   as   Charles   Taylor   and   Michael   Walzer8.   Agonistic   pluralism   is                                                                                                                           5

  Berlin   sets   up   the   difference   by   means   of   the   formula   “”I   prefer   coffee,   you   prefer   champagne.   We   have  different  tastes.  There  is  no  more  to  be  said’.  That  is  relativism”  (PI  p.9  the  emphasis  is  mine).         6  Mackie  (1977).     7   Williams   1982.   Williams   sets   vulgar   relativism   apart   from   what   he   calls   “appraisal   relativism”.   For   Williams,   moral   predicaments   between   distinct   moral   cultures   are   meaningful   only   when   we   face   actual   options,   it   is   that   the   criterion   would   be   settled   by   the   values   actually   shared   by   a     given   culture.   Agonistic  pluralism  cannot  be  well  framed  in  neither  of  them.      

4    

5     contrary  both  to  subjectivist  theories  of  values  and  to  cultural  relativism.  As  we  will  see,  if   the   argument’s   conclusion   ends   up   leading   us   to   a   kind   of   moral   skepticism   it   is   not   because  of  its  subjectivist’s  premises.      

 

(b)  Incommensurability      

From   the   fact   that   values   have   an   objective   nature   one   cannot   infers   that   they  

inevitably   clashed.   Berlin   needs   to   provide   another   principle,   the   principle   of   incommensurability,   through   which   he   shows   us   that   some   values   are   impossible   to   be   harmonized,  or  even  that  every  value  is  potentially  conflicting  with  each  other.  An  analogy   with   another   kind   of   incommensurability   principle   could   be   helpful   here.   Thomas   Khun   has  famously  stated  that  there  are  a  plenty  of  epistemic  values  appraised  by  the  scientific   community   but   at   some   occasions   -­‐   i.   e.   in   paradigm-­‐shifts   occasions   –   different   values   became   incommensurable.   So   simplicity,   for   instance,   could   be   more   important   than   achieving  unexpected  results  to  hold  scientists  down  to  old  theories,  but  at  the  same  time   the  new  empirical  gains  brought  by  the  new  theory  would  be  certainly  attractive  to  new   generations   of   researchers.   The   point   is   that   both   sides   can   assume   that   simplicity   and     “unexpectancy”   are   epistemic   values   although   they   do   not   dismiss   the   difficult   (but   rational)  choice  between  them.  What  we  are  facing  here  are  trade-­‐offs  of  values  and  this,   according  to  Khun,  is  completely  different  from  skepticism  concerning  epistemic  values   in  

general:  “[w]hat  I  am  denying  then  is  neither  the  existence  of  good  reasons  nor  that  these   reasons   are   of   the   sort   usually   described.   I   am,   however,   insisting   that   such   reasons   constitute  values  to  be  used  in  making  choices  rather  than  rules  of  choice”  (Kuhn  2003  p.   195).   The   same   theoretical   problem   could   be   answered   differently   by   two   scientists   equally   rational   and   motivated   to   find   out   the   best   theory.   It   happens   that   they   need   to   choose  between  values,  and  being  incommensurate  is  the  reason  why  they  need  to  choose.   So  we  could  say  that  for  Kuhn’s  philosophy  of  science  every  scientific  revolution  implies  a   “clash”   of   (epistemic)   values.   By   analogy   this   is   the   way   I   believe   Berlin’s   statements   concerning  the  “clash”  of  values  should  be  taken.     Consider  two  contrasting  forms  of  life,  for  example  a  public  life  full  of  grandiosity   and  a  modesty  private  life9.    Suppose  that  I  have  chosen  to  pursue  a  politically  engaged  life                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                               8

  See   for   example   Walzer’s   definition   of   “complex   egalitarianism”:   “My   own   claim   is   that   we   cannot   distribute  goods  to  men  and  women  until  we  understand  what  the  goods  mean,  what  parts  they  play,   how  they  are  created,  and  how  they  are  valued,  among  those  same  men  and  women.  Distributions  flow   out  of  and  are  relative  to  social  meanings”  (Walzer  1983).  For  Taylor’s  methodological  considerations,   see  Taylor  1985.     9     This   example   overlaps   Berlin’s   famous   interpretation   of   Machiavelli   as   “agonistic   thinker”:   the   Christian  morality  is  incompatible  with  the  “ruthless  pursuit  of  power”,  but  neither  of  them  should  be  

5    

6     and   because   of   that   I   had   chosen   to   hold   an   important   office   in   my   political   community.   For   me,   being   a   well-­‐renowned   authority   is   better   than   being   merely   an   activist.   But   the   same  does  not  happen  concerning  the  other  value  in  contrast:  the  security  of  a  familiar  life.   I  cannot  say  that  being  an  authority  is  always  better  than  enjoying  a  happy  and  flourishing   familiar   life   in   the   same   way   as   I   said   that   is   always   better   being   an   authority   than   a   grassroots  activist.  The  only  way  to  really  understand  the  meaning  of  my  personal  choices   is   to   understand   the   kinds   of   values   that   I   have   to   give   up.   This   conception   of   value-­‐ incommensurability  is  explored  by  Joseph  Raz.  In    a  process  of  moral  choice,   two  values,  A  

and  B,  are  incommensurate  if  it  is  not  the  case  that  A  is  better  than  B  or  B  is  better  than  A   and  at  the  same  time  A  and  B  are  not  equally  appraised.   What  Raz  has  in  mind  is  to  grasp   the  difference  between  value-­‐incommensurability  and  the  related  (but  different)  concepts   of   value-­‐equivalence,   and   value-­‐incommunicability.   A   and   B   are   equivalent   when   they   value   the   same   and   are   incommunicative   when   they   cannot   be   evaluated   by   the   same   agent.  On  the  contrary,  a  typical  incommensurable  situation  happen  when  the  possibility   of   relative   judgments   between   A   and   B   is   closed   off   even   though     it   is   acceptable   that   despite  not  being  the  same  they  are  both  important.  As  Raz  stated,  “incomparability  does   not   ensure   equality   of   merit   and   demerit.   It   does   not   mean   indifference.   It   marks   the   inability   of   reason   to   guide   our   action,   not   the   insignificance   of   our   choice”   (Raz   1986   p.   334).  According  to  this  definition  of  value-­‐incommensurability,  there  is  any  solution  to  our   moral  life  that  avoid  some  sort  of  choice.    Nor  could  we  conceive  an  impartial  principle  of   decision  to  help  us.    

   

(c)  Moral  Skepticism      

The   main   conclusion   so   far   is   that   (true)   values   cannot   be   subsumed   to   one  

another  (objectivity)  nor  we  hope  to  find  a  criterion  of  priority  or  systematization  among   them  (incommensurability).  Even  rational  and  reflected  solutions  of  moral  predicaments   cannot  avoid  a  grain  of  the  irrationality  of  choice.  If  it  is  a  true    that  we  face  moral  trade-­‐ offs,   any   attempt   to   dismiss   them   would   rise   skeptical   suspicious.   This   set   up   stringent   constrains  on  general  conceptions  of  morality.  Let’s  take  a  classical  moral  trade-­‐off  as  the   clash  between  the  rival  claims  of  equality  and  liberty.  Agonistic  pluralism  tells  us  that  it  is   impossible   to   show   that   there   is   only   one   right   relation   between   this   two   values   concerning  the  organization  of  our  political  life.  We  know  that  both  of  them  exist  and  are   important,  but  how  to  combine  them  is  something  completely  contingent.   Every    attempt                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                               stated  as  the  final  moral  truth.  The  first  task  of  political  philosophy  is  to  recognize  the  potentials  clash   among  them.  See  his  essay  “The  Originality  of  Machiavelli”.    

6    

7     to  harmonize  the  parties  under  a  single  conception  represent  in  fact  a  sort  of  moral  hoax   in   which   we   coercively   turn   a   single   value   into   the   only   moral   possibility.   “Monistic”   theories   of   human   values   (as   Marxism   and   Utilitarianism)   are   morally   wrong   for   Berlin   because  they  are  conceptually  impossible.      

 

 This  conclusion  raises  a  claim  of  moral  skepticism  concerning  normative  general  

principles.   Ronald   Dworkin   (2007)   has   defined   two   clusters   of   skeptical   arguments   against  cognitivists  accounts  of  moral  reasoning,  i.  e.  if  moral  propositions  have  truth-­‐or-­‐ falsehood   ontology.   In   the   first   set   he   placed   those   theories   that   are   skeptical   about   the   very  possibility  of  assuming  truth  or  falsehood  to  our  moral  discourse.  This  general  views   are  called  “external  skepticism”  because  they  try  to  evaluate  the  nature  of  moral  reasoning   from   the   outside   –   normally   from   a   physicalist   point   of   view.   The   second   kind   is   called   “internal”   skepticism   and   its   strategy   is   to   show   that   in   spite   of   our   capacity   to   produce   meaningful   propositions   in   the   moral   sphere,   there   is   an   indeterminacy   concerning   the   rights   ways   of   set   general   principles   up   in   that   dimension.   We   cannot   ground   our   judgments   because   values   are   not   as   objective   or   indisputable   as   empirical   data.   Clearly   Berlin’s   argument   cannot   be   placed   under   the   label   of   “external”   skepticism   due   to   its   objectivistic   premises   (strong   ones   as   a   matter   of   fact),   what   brings   it   to   the   “internal”   label.  However  I  do  not  think  that  agonistic  pluralism  fits  well  here  too.  It  is  skeptical  only   against   “monistic”   solutions   not   about   the   nature   of   the   values   per   se.     It   is   neither   skeptical   about   the   worth   of   the   struggle   for   bring   these   values   up.   However   we   can   use   the  label  loosely  to  characterized  agonistic  pluralism  conclusions.   One   way   to   see   the   argument   in   action   is   showing   Berlin’s   criticism   against   “utopian  projects”.  Utopian  projects  are  moral  theories  that  frame  ideally  a  conception  of   good  life  for  a  political  community.  Every  formulation  of  these  utopian  scenarios  rests  on   what  we  could  call  “the  monistic  fallacy”:  if  A  is  a  human  good  and  B  is  a  human  good,  so  A   and  B  are  to  be  logical  consistent  (cf.  DU  p.  24-­‐25).  But  as  we  have  already  shown  agonistic   pluralism   denies   the   very   possibility   of   monism’s   conceptual   soundness.   Marxist   and   utilitarian  projects  are  the  usual  targets  here.  But  even  those  “regulative  ideals”  so  easily   assumed  by  Kantians  or  soft-­‐headed  reformists,  would  be  denied  by  the  moral  skepticism.   The   assumption   that   universal   principles   are   worthwhile,   even   if   they   fall   short   of   the   ideal,   would   carry   the   fallacy   too.   Different   demands   presented   into   the   same   piece   of   constitution   would   lead   to   morally   unsolvable   cases   when   they   appeal   to   different   fundamental   values.   Public   dignity   and   freedom   of   expression,   for   instance,   could   not   be   harmonized   through   a   general   conception   of   justice,   considering   that   each   claim   is   grounded  in  a  different  value.  To  say  that  is  always  morally  right  assuring  people’s  right  to   expression  even  if  they  could  harm  minorities,  would  be  the  same  as  giving  foundational   7    

8     priority   to   liberty   over   fraternity,   or   maybe   to   individual   rights   against   communal   goals,   and  so  forth.     To   use   a   formulation   that   has   been   offered   by   Kolakowski,   utopian   phrases   are   self-­‐defeating   (“equality   thorough   an   enlighten   vanguard”   or   “fraternity   via   strength”)   once   they   try   to   reduce   one   value   into   another10.   The   only   kind   of   intellectual   help   that   philosophers  and  political  authors  could  offer  are  refined  interpretations  of  our  common   history,  exploring  the  many  possibilities  of  combined  values  and  teaching  us  how  we  can   live   in   a   pluralistic   world.     In   essence   these   are   the   same   aims   of   moral   theory   that   one   finds  in  Williams,  Walzer,  Gray,  Rorty  and  Lebrun11.    

2.  The  role  of  “negative”  liberty      

How  Berlin  can  justify  his  normative  premises?   12  Or  to  put  it  slightly  different,  in  

which  epistemic  basis  can  we  state  the  objectivity  and  the  incommensurability  of  values?  I   believe  that  the  only  way  to  grasp  it  is  analyzing  the  role  that  our  faculty  of  choice  assumes   in  his  work.  Berlin’s  conception  of  liberty,  or  more  specifically,  negative  liberty,  works  as   the  moral  criterion  we  have  been  looking  for.  To  do  that  it  is  necessary  first  to  cope  with   Berlin’s  famous  essay  “Two  Concepts  of  Liberty”  (1958  TCL).  I  would  like  to  avoid  the  vast   bibliography   concerning   what   it   really   states   or   whether   Berlin’s   historical   picture   is   accurate   or   not,   to   focus   on   a   more   interesting   task:   to   determine   what   the   conception   implies  normatively.     Berlin’s   definition   of   liberty,   as   a   human   feature,   is   not   different   from   that  

 

minimalist   definition   offered   by   Hobbes   when   he   says   that   a   free   man   is   absent   from   impediments   to   do   what   he   wants   (Hobbes   [1651]   1996   cap.   21,   cf.   TCL   p.   195   n.1).                                                                                                                           10

  Kolakowski   1981   p.   240.   However,   Kolakowski   himself   sets   up   a   distinction   that   I   accept   between   “constitutive”  and  “regulative”  uses  of  the  utopian  ideas  that  is  completely  absent  in  Berlin’s  critique.    

  11

 Cf.  for  instance  Gray  1993  (a)  p.  292;  Rorty  1995  p.  587-­‐588  ;  Lebrun  1981  pp.  115-­‐119.  

12

  We   could   contrast   the   argument   of   normative   pluralism   for   moral   theory   with   a   general   argument   that   Berlin   usually   access   philosophical   arguments   overall.   Against   logical   positivism,   for   instance,   we   could  not  “reconstruct”  the  objective  world  thought  a  minimal  set  of  basic,  or  atomic,  statements.  There   is   not   –   as   assumed   by   logical   positivism   –   a   genuinely   type   of   sentence   –   declarative   statements   for   example  -­‐  from  which  we  can  derive  all  the  rest  of  meaningful  propositions.  Even  “deflationary”  projects   as  the  ordinary  language  analysis  do  it  better  because  it  assumes  that  ordinary  statements  are  the  real   human   statements   from   which   everything   is   derived.   Also   here,   Berlin   is   struggling   against   the   belief     that  “all  propositions  must  in  principle  be  either  translatable  into,  or  at  any  rate  in  some  way  connected   with,  the  approved  type  of  sentences  (which  alone  fully  reflect  ‘the  structure  of  reality’),  or  else  suffer   from  defects  which  must  either  be  explained  away  or  palliated  by  special  logical  ‘treatment’,  or,  if  they   prove  too  recalcitrant,  removed  with  their  owners  beyond  logical  pale”  (LT  p.  79).  From  the  existence  of   an   objective   reality   (physical   and   moral)   it   does   not   implies   that   we   hold   a   unique   way   to   square   it   down.  There  are  many  (and  conflicting)  possibilities  to  do  that.    

8    

9     Thence   the   essay   was   not   aiming   for   the   metaphysical   meaning   of   liberty   or   even     questioning  the  place  of  personal  liberty  as  a  condition  of  possibility  for  a  meaningful  life.   It  addresses  a  different  question:  historically  liberty  has  assumed  a   value   in  our  societies   and  despite  its  centrality  it  has  a  double  (and  misleading)  meaning.  One  way  to  grasp  the   difference  according  to  Berlin  is  paying  attention  to  the  kind  of  answer  each  interpretation   give   to   the   problem   of   coercion.   Famously,   negative   liberty   is   defined   as   a   moral   elbow   room,   a   space   where   the   agents   are   free   from   intervention   of   states   or   communities   and   positive   liberty   as   a   desire   to   be   a   subject   not   an   object,   the   desire   to   lead   my   own   life   autonomously13.    

If  we  had  accepted  the  agonistic  pluralism  account  of  the  value’s  nature,  we  could  

have  understood  the  two  senses  of  liberty  as  two  distinct  (objective  and  incommensurate)   values:   freedom   for   coercion   and   rational   self-­‐government.   We   can   appraise   both,   however  hardly  ever  could  we  avoid  choosing  between  them.  The  problem  of  legitimacy  of     human   rights   offers   us   an   example   of   predicament   that   Berlin   is   drag   our   attention   to.   What   would   be   its   plausibility   if   they   depended   only   on   the   effective   choice   of   those   affected  by  them?  Those  who  work  with  the  promotion  of  human  rights  cannot  count  with   effective  consentient  of  those  who  are  helped  by  them.  On  the  contrary,  they  often  claim   that  those  rights  are   the  moral  conditions  through  which   valuable   choices  are  made.  Once   at  the  limit  even  an  educational  system  (for  those  reluctant  students  perhaps)  would  not   be   justified   if   the   effective   consciousness   of   empirical   agents   is   the   sole   ground   of   moral   evaluation.  This  is  the  reason  why  other  values  will  clash  with  (negative)  liberty.  As  well   perceived  by  Berlin  himself:  Liberty  could  not  be  the  only  aim  of  men,  but  at  the  same  time   “nothing  is  gained  by  a  confusion  of  terms”  (TCL  p.  197).       However,  hardly  is  it  the  whole  story.    The  human  faculty  for  choosing  -­‐  to  exercise   its   “negative”   liberty   -­‐   is   a   precondition   to   any   context   of   value   trade-­‐off.   To   better   understand   the   conception   of   negative   liberty   and   realize   how   it   should   be   assumed   beforehand   as   a   universal   precondition   of   the   values   themselves,   we   have   to   set   up   a   distinction  between  liberty’s   definition   on  one  hand,  and  liberty’s   criterion  of  validity     on   the  other:    

                                                                                                                         

13

 We  can  summarized  this  difference  respectively  through  the  questions  “what  is  the  area   within  which   the  subject  –  a  person  is  or  should  be  left  to  do  or  be  what  he  is  able  to  do  or  be  without  interference  by   other  people?”  and  “What,  or  who,  is  the  source  of  control  or  interference  that  can  determine  someone   to  do,  or  be,  this  rather  than  that?”  (TCL  p.  194).  

9    

10     (i)

Definition:   Liberty   (Negative)   is   a   discretion   to   act   according   to   individuals  

desires,  without    suffering  the  interference  of  others  other  than  the  agent  itself   during  the  process.   (ii)

Criterion  of  Validity:  the  only  way  to  decide  what  counts  as  interference  should  

be  judged  by  the  agent’s  own  point  of  view.     So   according     to   the   berlinian   definition   of   negative   liberty,   its   value   is   in   danger   if   and   only  if  (i)  X’s  liberty  is  bound  to  be  restricted  and  (ii)  X   believe  that  it  is  the  case  that  his   liberty   is   restricted.   In   other   words:   liberty   here   refers   to   the   own   believes   that   X   hs   concerning  his  own  liberty.      

On  this  account  every  action  of  enforcement  is  potentially  coercive  from  the  agent  

point  of  view.  However  there  is  a  kind  of  coercion  that  ,  despite  its  conflict  with  liberty,  has   the  appearance  of  a  deeper  freedom  appealing  to  the  “true”  essence  of  human  beings.  Even   though   our   empirical   selves   could   resist,   the   argument   goes,   there   is     “an   occult   entity   –   their   latent   rational   will,   or   their   ‘true’   purpose   –   and   that   this   entity,   although   it   is   believed  by  all  that  they  overtly  feel  and  do  and  say,  is  their  ‘real’  self  of  which  the  poor   empirical   self   […]   may   know   nothing”   (TCL   p.   205).     So   once   we   accept   this   characterization   of   liberty   as   an   objective   value   we   ought   to   concede   that   there   is   an   important   conceptual   distinction   between   threatening   X’s   liberty   simpliciter   (for   the   purpose  of  other  value  as  equality  or  fraternity)  and  threatening  X’s  liberty  because  it  is   better  to  X  to  do  it  (on  the  name  of  a  deeper  “I”)  in  such  a  way  that  at  the  end  there  is  no   violation   at   all!.   Berlin   has   called   this   rhetorical   device   rationalism’s   “magic   transformation”   due   to   how   it   reduces   value’s   incommensurability   to   only   one   easy   solution.  “It  is  one  thing  to  say  that  I  may  be  coerced  for  my  good  […]  it  is  another  that  if  it   is   my   good,   than   I   am   not   being   coerced”   (TCP   p.   205).   In   fact,   to   understand   Berlin’s   skepticism  against  normative  principles  and  “utopian  projects”  in  general  we  should  pay   attention  to  the  way  he  frames  the  value  of  liberty.  If  it  is  the  very  possibility  to  choose  our   ideas  of  good  and  a  meaningful  life,  and  if  this  possibility  is  an  objective  value  shared  by   any  group  of  human  beings,  then  normative  reasoning  should  avoid  concealing  particular   choices   and   preferences   in   the   kingdom   of   ends   through   a   dubious   theory   of   a   split   self:   part   empirical   and   conscious,   part   rational   and   unconscious.   Assuming   that   liberty   of   conscience   and   the  protection  of  people’s  own  decisions  is  taken  for   granted,  it  is  barely   improbable   that   someone   could   state   a   moral   principle,   or   any   set   of   them,   that   would   satisfied  the  highly  demanded  requirements  of  negative  liberty.    

Giving  normative  priority  to  actual  preferences  and  self-­‐awareness  is  a  clever  way  

to  block  off  utopian  thinking.  Hardly  ever  people  are  willing  to  confront  antagonist  moral   10    

11     reasoning  with  an  open-­‐minded  stance  especially  when  these  arguments  upset  the  whole   practices   and   valuable   choices   made   by   us14.   The   burden   of   proof   against   our   actual   desires  and  beliefs  is  on  the  side  of  utopias.  However  attractive  this  picture  is  it  inevitably   will   turn   down   any   normative   principle   that   clash   with   the   contents   of   negative   liberty   even  though  purely  regulative  ones.  Take  for  instance  an  egalitarian  conception  of  justice   strongly  committed  with  a  more  egalitarian  distribution  of  wealth.  Taking  our  societies  as   they  are  it  is  almost  impossible  that  this  redistribution  -­‐  maybe  supported  by  the  value  of   equality   –   could   be   accepted.   Actual   political   agents   will   certainly   antagonize   with   it,   seeing  it  as  an  infringement  of  their  liberty.  Although  agonistic  pluralism  would  grant  the   legitimacy   of   redistribution   per  se   it   remains   as   a   way   of   coercion.   Any   attempt   to   avoid   this  conclusion  would  mean  to  “bypass”  the  “real”  citizens  with  their  actual  desires,  beliefs   and  fears.  There  are  no  normative  principles  that  could  avoid  the  priority  of  real  politics15.   Stated   as   it   is   agonistic   pluralism   cannot   avoid   taking   every   moral   generalization   or   principle  as  coercive  as  a  terrifying  dystopia.   Once   we   assume   individual   rights   as   the   priority   of   people’s   actual   decisions   it   would  be  barely  impossible  that  someone  could  state  a  moral  principle,  or  any  set  of  them,   that   would   not   be   coercive   in   some   instance.   Philosophical   liberalism   as   a   general   set   of   regulative   principles   for   the   evaluation   of   social   institutions   is   undermined   by   agonistic   pluralism  as  an  impossible  goal.  Its  ideal  of  consensual  consentient  between  equals  is  just   one  more  utopian  temptation16.        

3.  Liberalism  and  the  “Berlinian  Paradox”     If   my   crude   interpretation   of   the   argument   so   far   has   got   the   point   I   can   see   one   possible  flaw  in  agonistic’s  argument.  This  problem,  in  my  view,  is  so  decisive  that  it  leads   agonistic   pluralism   towards   a   dead-­‐end.   I   suggest   calling   it   “the   Berlinian   Paradox”   –   to   highlight  how  it  is  transmitted  to  other  kinds  of  agonistic  reasoning  in  political  theory.   Before   exploring   the   paradox   I   intend   to   state   briefly   what   are   the   political   commitments   supported   by   an   agonistic   account   of   values.   Although   the   self-­‐effacing   nature  of  politics  in  Berlin’s  work,  it  is  quite  easy  to  assume  that  his  opinions  match  with   what   we   could   call   a   “classical”   liberalism   and   a   commitment   to   a   free   and   pluralistic   society:                                                                                                                           14

 One  could  add:  especially  when  they  are  favored  by  status  quo.  

 

15

 Priority  in  the  sense  argued  by  Walzer  (1981)  and  Rorty  (1991).  I  shall  return  to  this  question  later.      

 

16

 For  the  definition  of  philosophical  liberalism  that  I  have  in  mind  here,  see  Waldron  1987.    

11    

12       pluralism,  with  the  measure  of  ‘negative’  liberty  that  it  entails,  seems  to   me  a  truer  and  more  humane  ideal  than  the  goals  of  those  who  seek  in   the  great  disciplined,  authoritarian  structures  the  ideal  of  ‘positive’  self-­‐ mastery  […]  It  is  truer,  because  it  does,  at  least,  recognize  the  fact  that   human  goals  are  many,  not  all  of  them  commensurable,  and  in  perpetual   rivalry  with  one  another  (TCL  p.  241).     We   might   grasp   what   a   pluralistic   society   mean   through   the   institutional   background   necessary  to  assure  (the  truth)  that  human  goals  are  many.  Individual  rights  as  freedom  of   speech  and  conscience,  liberty  of  association  and  the  rule  of  law  are  the  usual  liberal  tools   to  get  it17.  Consequentially  in  a  pluralistic  society  the  main  institutional  framework  works   by  a  principle  of  toleration  concerning  different  opinions  and  styles  of  life,  respecting  the   ethical  decisions  made  by  the  individuals.  Liberalism  -­‐  as  a  political  theory  concerned  with   legal   protection   of   individual   choices   -­‐   seems   almost   as   a   natural   conclusion   of   agonistic   pluralism.  Negative  liberty  entails  the  priority  of  right  over  good.    

The  Berlinian  paradox  arises  when  one  pose  the  question:  why   should  we  struggle  

for  that  kind  of  society?  Why  are  pluralistic  societies  essentially  better  than  monistic  ones?   Taking  the  last  as  de  facto  possibility  in  human  historic    what  kind  of  reason  do  we  have  to   favor  a  de  jure  pluralistic  society  against  the  facts?  Perhaps  because  they  count  with  a  true   picture   of   human   values,   or   because   only   in   these   kind   of   societies   all   the   agonistic   predicaments   could   be   appraised.   Actually   relying   upon   their   premises   it   is   hard   not   to   state   the   moral   truth   of   value   pluralism.   We   have   to   conceive   moral   pluralism   as   an   objective  truth  -­‐  just  like  liberty  and  equality  are  also  objective  true  values  for  Berlin.    It   would  be  impossible  to  conceive  a  human  society  in  which  moral  pluralism  (de  facto)  does   not   occur.   The   fact   that   it   is   not   always   recognized   or   estimated   equally   would   be   a   historical   contingency   that   we   can   only   lament   and   try   to   avoid.   Arguing   for   agonistic   pluralism   is   to   carry   through   liberalism   or   liberal   institutions   against   all   sort   of   hostile   forms   of   life,   whether   secularized   or   not.     Far   from   being   an   exaggerated   interpretation,   Berlin   keep   telling   us,   perhaps   due   to   his   historical   context,   how   the   very   possibility   of   political  theory  depends  on  a  pluralistic  framework,  and  how  we  should  strive  to  protect  it   against  the  temptation  of  monistic  thoughts18.                                                                                                                              

17

  Nevertheless   we   should   note   that   the   effective   participation   on   the   main   political   decision-­‐process   conceived   in   the   political   rights   is   more   controversial   due   to   the   argument.   It   is   possible   to   conceive   pluralism  without  participation.  The  only  thing  we  need  is  an  affective  principle  of  toleration.         18   For   example,   “Unless   political   philosophy   is   confined   to   the   analysis   of   concepts   or   expressions,   it   can   be   pursued   consistently   only   in   a   pluralistic,   or   potentially   pluralistic,   society   […]   rigid   monism   is   compatible  with  philosophical  analysis  only  in  theory”  (PTSE  p.  150).  

12    

13      

Following   the   argument   we   can   state   that   moral   pluralism   supports   liberal  

institutions,   it   gives   us   general   and   strong   reasons   turn   down   coercive   ways   of   living.   Otherwise  moral  pluralism  itself  would  be  just  that:  a  culture-­‐specific  experience  allowed   by  contingent  historical  developments  in  which  the  values  and  its  organization  are  nothing   more   than   subjective   creations.     This   “non-­‐foundational”   route   bump   into   the   late   statement   that   if   a   pluralistic   society   should   be   promoted   and   certain   institutional   schemes  are  necessary,  against  the  countless  possible  cultural  experience,  then  the  reason   why  we  should  strive  for  it  was  that  pluralistic  societies  are  better  than  monistic  ones  and   they  are  better   just  because  they  recognize  the  true  value  of  personal  liberty.  In  spite  of  a   mere   exposition   of   epistemic   premises,   the   agonistic   argument   established   a   normative   criterion  to  political  theory,  a  general  principle  to  favor   one  kind  of  society  among  others.   This  paradox  can  be  summarized  as  follow:     (P1):  Moral  pluralism  is  true  (or,  it  is  the  case  that  values  can  clash)   (P2):   One   cannot   state   effectively   that   (P1)   unless   the   recognition   and   promotion   (institutionally)   of   a   particular   kind   of   society   –   pluralistic   –   in   which   a   specific   value   –   negative  liberty  –  is  granted.   (C):  There  are  in  fact  societies  that  are  different  from  (P2),  probably  because  they  denied   (P1)   (it   is   not   the   case   that   values   can   clash),   and   so   are   illegitimate   from   agonistic   pluralism’s  point  of  view.     Suppose    that  now  we  do  not  want  to  accept  (C)’s  validity  maybe  because  it  is  at  odd  with   the   openness   of   agonistic   pluralism,   maybe   because   it   sounds   “monistic”   enough   to   support   just   one   kind   of   political   arrangement   where   negative   liberty   (individual   rights)   have  priority  over  other  values  (there  are   no  general  normative  principles).  Therefore  we   would   like   to   recognize   negative   liberty   as   one   value   among   others,   perhaps   stating   something  as:     (P3):   Moral   pluralism   is   true   for   us   (or,   it   is   the   case   that   values   can   clash   in   societies   where  negative  liberty  has  some  priority  over  other  values).     So,    

13    

14     (C’):  There  are  in  fact  societies  that  are  different  from  (P2),  probably  because  they  denied   (P1)  (it  is  not  the  case  that  values  can  clash),  but  they  are  just  one  more  human  possibility   among  many  -­‐  equally  legitimated  -­‐  others.       As   soon   as   we   add   (P3)   -­‐   trying   to   avoid   the   uneasy   (C)   -­‐   we   upset   the   whole   argument   because   we   had   already   concluded   in   the   first   section   that   agonistic   pluralism   as   an   account   of   moral   pluralism   was   not   a   cultural-­‐specific   argument.   It   has   absolute   foundations.  It  implies  that  we  ought  to  assume  that  (P1)  is  false,  perhaps  reframing  it  as   something  like:     (P1’):  Moral  pluralism  is  true  for  S,  where  S  is  already  a  pluralistic  society.     This   result   obliges   us   to   express   serious   misgivings   about   the   most   original   element   of   Berlin’s   argument,   i.   e.   its   objectivity.   We   can   no   longer   take   moral   pluralism   as   a   moral  

truth  about  the  world19.   A   tragic   choice   has   to   make   agonistic   pluralism:   unless   one   secludes   the   true   account   of   moral   pluralism   to   pluralistic   societies   (hence:   liberal),   and   committing   itself   with   cultural   and   historic   relativism   about   values,   he   cannot   avoid   to   stand   for   general   normative   prescriptions   or   ideals   against   non-­‐liberal   ways   of   life.   If   it   is   so,   at   least   the   priority   of   individual   rights   and   the   institutionalization   of   tolerance   take   up   the   form   of   general  principles  of  justice.        

4.  Varieties  of  political  liberalism      

I   lack   time   (or   maybe   skills)   to   sum   up   the   types   of   philosophical   foundations   to  

liberalism   available   in   the   contemporary   debate.   Nevertheless   any   variety   of   liberalism   invariably   has   to   deal   with   moral   pluralism   and,   more   specifically,   with   the   hard   task   of   giving   a   normative   ground   to   the   principle   of   tolerance.   As   Rawls   said   in   Political  

Liberalism,   moral   pluralism   “is   a   permanent   feature   of   the   public   culture   of   democracy”   (Rawls   2005   p.   36).   One   possible   way   to   establish   that   is   trying   to   contrast   the   kinds   of   normative  foundation  (and  the  practical  consequences  derived  from  that)  that  the  concept  

                                                                                                                        19

  “[I]f   value-­‐pluralisms   is   correct,   then   these   are   truths,   correct   moral   beliefs   about   the   world   […]   it   is   a   species  of  moral  realism,  which  we  shall  call  objective  pluralism”  (Gray  1995  p.  71).  

14    

15     of   tolerance   acquires20.   Why   should   I   constrain   myself   or   what   gives   authority   to   states   when   I   am   obliged   to   comply   with   a   rule   that   I   cannot   accept   due   to   moral   reasons.   For   example,   if   we   are   tempt   to   conceive   society   as   a   composition   of   self-­‐interested   parties   trying  to  impose  their  desires  (whether  moral  or  not)  upon  each  other,  moral  pluralism  is   seemed  as  a  “second-­‐best”  result  -­‐  and  toleration  collapse  into  a  modus  vivendi.  Values  are   only   shared   desires   and   tolerance   itself   is   not   a   normative   concept   but   a   maxim   of   prudence.  Justice    is  a  profitable  contract  capable  of  getting  mutual  protection.        

It  is  easy  to  see  that  what  Isaiah  Berlin  had  in  mind  when  he  thought  about  moral  

pluralism   was   something   different.   Also   it   is   difficult   to   extract   a   precise   political   theory   from   Berlin’s   works   even   though   he   is   often   thought   as   a   classical   liberal.   There   is   a   conceptual   contradiction   between   the   skeptical   element   of   agonistic   pluralism   and   its   normative   requirements.   However,   one   of   the   paradox’s   horns   has   led   us   to   a   non-­‐ foundational   interpretation   of   agonistic   liberalism   where   far   from   being   a   predicament,   skepticism  is  a  solution.  This  radical  interpretation  finds  its  way  through  the  works  of  self-­‐ conceived   non-­‐foundational   authors   in   moral   theory   as   John   Gray,   Michael   Waltzer,   Bernard  Williams  and  (in  a  neopragmatic  fashion)  Richard  Rorty21.  Commonly  they  shared   (i)   an   agonistic   account   of   moral   pluralism,   (ii)   a   strong   skepticism   concerning   moral   theory,  and  (iii)  an  explicit  commitment  to  liberalism  as  a  valuable  practice  or  form  of  life.   Nevertheless   their   differences,   each   of   them   express   itself   against   foundational   or   “philosophical”   accounts   of   political   theory.   Liberal   and   democratic   institutions   such   as   toleration,  civic  rights  and  democratic  participation  are  appraised  as  shared  practices  not   just   because   they   express   deep   moral   principles.   Political   liberalism   here   is   a   practical   solution  to  a  moral  skepticism  concerning  moral  pluralism.    

To  evaluate  the  soundness  of  the  views  present  in  my  paper  I  would  like  to  track  

the   berlinian   paradox   down   into   the   main   arguments   of   two   theories   of   political   liberalism:   the   “agonistic   liberalism”   of   John   Gray,   and   the   “postmodern   (bourgeoise)   liberalism”   of   Richard   Rorty.   At   the   end,   I’ll   make   an   attempt   to   deal   with   the   moral   pluralism  argument  from  a  different  perspective.      

 

(a)  Agonistic  Liberalism                                                                                                                            

20

 In  my  work  in  progress  I  am  pursuing  to  establish  four  types  of  philosophical  foundations  each  of  them   related   with   a   particular   branch   of   liberal   theory:   (i)   agonistic/non-­‐foundational   liberalism,   (ii)   neo-­‐ hobbesian   liberalism,   (iii)   perfectionist   liberalism   and   (iv)   egalitarian   liberalism.   Only   the   last   two   varieties  are  expect  to  find  out  a  explicitly  normative  principle  to  support  their  theories.  In  the  end  of   this  paper  I  shall  try  to  sketch  an  egalitarian  answer  to  the  agonistic  pluralist  conclusion.   21   For   example:   Gray   (1993,   1995(a)),   Walzer   (1981,   1985),   Williams   (1985,   [1996]   2009)   and   Rorty   (1983,  1991).  Other  important  thinker  when  it  comes  to  this  field  in  the  Brazilian  academic  world  is  the   political  work  of  the  French  philosopher  Gerard  Lebrun  ([1984]  2003).  

15    

16       John   Gray   defines   its   liberalism   as   “an   application   in   political   philosophy   of   the   moral   theory   of   value-­‐pluralism”   (Gray   1995(a)   p.   69).   However,   at   the   same   time,   it   shares  the  non-­‐foundational  interpretation  of  the  berlinian  paradox:     “for  us  […]    for  whom  the  practice  of  autonomy  is  an  essential  part  of  the   good   life   and   for   whom   individualism   and   pluralism   are   an   historical   fate,  a  liberal  civil  society  is  one  in  which  the  richest  diversity  of  forms   of   flourishing   is   most   likely   to   be   achieved.   This   result   is   avowedly     culture-­‐specific,  and  it  is  not  meant  to  be  universalized”  (Gray  1997(b)   p.  324  stress  marks  added).       A  liberal  form  of  political  organization  with  all  the  institutional  background  one  requires  is   worth  because  it  “has  the  advantage,  for  virtually  all  modern  peoples,  that  in  it  epistemic   freedoms   are   protected”   (p.   324).     However,   without   these   epistemic   advantages   presented  in  liberal  institutions,  the  very  fact  of  moral  pluralism  would  not  be  recognized   as   such.   How   come   Gray   could   support   at   same   time   the   moral   contingency   of   liberal   institutions  and  the  necessary  value  of  moral  pluralism  of  which  liberal  institutions  are  the   cognitive   conditions   of   possibility?   Gray   typically   answers   this   question   with   a   cognitive   distinction   between   a   liberal   philosophy   on   one   hand   –   unbearable   in   face   of   agonistic   pluralism   –   and   a   liberal   tradition   embedded   into   our   modern   institutions   on   the   other.   We   should   keep   sustaining   our   institutions   and,   specially,   the   toleration   present   into   the   modern  civil  society  (cf.  p.  328).      

The   first   problem   with   Gray’s   account   is   the   skepticism   about   the  

“universalization”   of   liberal   institutions.   What   reasons   an   ardent   secular   “monist”   could   find  in  a  civil  society  full  of  religious  practices  and  arguments?  From   his  point  of  view  our   tradition   is   not   enough   perhaps   because   it   allowed   just   this   kind   of   reprehensible   situation.  For  the  atheist  we  would  do  better  with  a  completely  secularized  public  sphere.   Obviously   this   reasoning   will   bring   a   political   clash   to   the   public   life.   How   to   avoid   the  

modus  vivendi  conclusion?  Gray  asks  for  the  “moderation”  of  our  demands  on  each  other,   and  a  peaceful  recognition  of  differences  (cf.  Gray  1995(b)  p.  30).  In  other  words:  he  asks   for  a  principle  of  toleration.  But  it  cannot  work  out  unless  the  parties  -­‐  or  in  our  case  the   fanatic  secularist  -­‐  recognized  that  moral  pluralism  itself  is  a  moral  truth  and  that  it  entails   some  normative  priorities  to  be  effective.  Otherwise,  from  people’s  point  of  view,  the  only   way  to  settled  down  toleration  is  through  a  peaceful  compromise  between   political  forces   (not   moral   values)   that   respect   adversaries   bargain’s   power   (not   the   possible   value   of   their  commitments).    

16    

17      

Besides   this   stability   problem,   agonistic   liberalism   has   to   cope   with   the  

institutional  conditions  to  incommensurability.  Certainly  a  predictable  problem  it  is  once   we   realized   what   the   moral   truth   of   Berlin’s   argument   had   entangled.   If   our     historical   institutions   are   settled   up   on   universalistic   principles,   struggle   for   it   implies   struggle   for   some   sort   of   universal   claims   concerning   personal   liberty,   equal   conditions   and   human   dignity.   Why   should   we   value   equal   rights   if   only   the   existence   of   liberty   is   necessary   to   foster  moral  pluralism?  A  cast  system  or  a  deeply  unjust  society  could  be  as  “pluralistic”  as   a  standard  liberal  democracy.      

Both   problems   reflect,   in   my   opinion,   the   predicament   of   the   berlian   paradox:  

either  we  stand  for  the  objectivity  of  moral  pluralism  and  are  prepared  to  give  it  a  explicit   normative   foundation   -­‐   blaming   the   fanatic   atheist   for   moral   reasons   -­‐   or   the   argument   collapse   into   a   modus   vivendi   where   even   the   moral   pluralism   itself   is   a   contingent   arrangement.   The   fact   that   many   agonistic   authors   refer   their   arguments   back   to   the   Judith   Shklar   notion   of   “liberalism   of   fear”   (Shklar   2004),   reveals   the   tendency   of   this   theory   to   coincide   with   a   kind   liberalism   very   akin   to   subjectivism   about   value   and   skepticism  about  moral  pluralism  as  a  normative  (and  not  a  prudential)  concept.       (b)  Postmodern  Liberalism     […]      

5.  Conclusion      

I   would   like   to   conclude   my   paper   with   a   few   appointments   concerning   the   way  

how   I   am   inclined   to   conceive   the   relation   between   moral   pluralism   and   political   liberalism.  They  are  quite  general  and  insufficient  to  hold  together  a  systematic  view.  How   I  understand  it,  agonistic  pluralism  is  not  the  better  ground  for  a  liberal  theory.  The  main   reason  why  it  is  so  it  is  because  these  theories  do  not  construct  a  manageable  principle  of   toleration.      

As   we   already   said,   either   as   a   skeptical   or   a   normative   conception,   moral  

pluralism  is  the  essential  part  of  any  kind  of  political  liberalism.  However,  the  first  thing  to   note  is  that  we  can  defend  moral  pluralism  as  an  objective  and  appraised  concept  and,  at   same   time,   reject   its   “agonistic”   fashion.   Once   we   realized   the   “overobjectification”22   on                                                                                                                           22

 Thomas  Nagel  drags  our  attention  to  the  danger  of  giving  too  much  objectivity  to  our  values,  as  they   are  completely  independent  from  human  contexts  (cf.  Nagel  1979  pp.  162-­‐163).      

17    

18     Berlin’s   account   of   values   it   becomes   highly   questionable   how   strong   his   notion   of   negative  liberty  is.  The  negative  liberty’s  criterion  of  justification  states  that  only  personal   consciences   can   mark   the   boundaries   of   a   non-­‐coercive   action.     No   one   can   be   coerced   without   knowing   it.     If   for   material   reasons   the   agents   are   unable   to   express   coherently   their   real   desires   or   the   act   of   choice   means   almost   nothing,   liberty   maintains   its   value.   Even  more  problematic  is  the  implication  that,  to  stay  with  our  previous  example,  anykind   of   redistribution,   for   example,   is   as   coercive   as   the   lack   of   means   of   living   or   the   lost   of   other  fundamental  liberty  as  the  rule  of  law.  Dworkin  has  raised  the  right  question  when   he   asked   why   not   define   liberty   as   a   “freedom   to   do   whatever   you   like   so   long   as     you   respect   the   moral   rights,   properly   understood,   of   others”?   (Dworkin   2006   p.   112   stress   mark  added).  Does  it  make  sense  to  attribute  moral  value  to  a  notion  according  to  that  it  is   legitimate  to  prohibited  public  accepted  rules  of  appropriation  even  in  contexts  of  misery   and   depriving?   It   is   not   solely   “to   do   whatever   we   want”   what   we   value   in   a   free   life.   Probably  we  should  restate  its  criterion  of  justification  in  such  a  way  that  it  were  possible   to  include  shared  intuitions  about  the  intrinsic  value  of  human  life  and  social  cooperation.   Rights   are   fundamental   to   liberalism   and   basic   rights   give   us   important   forms   of   protection  and  control  over  our  lives,  but  they  need  to  be  justified  by  shared  standards  to   be  a  reasonable  idea23.   Secondly,  moral  skepticism  it  is  a   non  sequitur   on  Berlin’s  argument.    As  stated  by  

 

Thomas   Scanlon,   moral   inquiry   does   not   imply   “a   single   unified   set   of   substantive   principles   to   which   we   can   appeal   to   decide   which   things   have   [the]   property   [of   moral   wrongness]”   (Scanlon   1992   p.   11).   One   thing   is   to   turn   down   comprehensive   ethical   theories   as   a   solution   to   political   matters   -­‐   what   was   indeed   a   crucial   role   of   Berlin’s   works.  Another  is  to  show  doubts  about  any  normative  principle.  There  is  a  fundamental   distinction  between  the  reasons  used  for  justify  publicly  coercion  and  the  reasons  one  can   use  to  set  the  goals  of  his  life.  Mixing  them  into  the  general  label  of  “values”  implies  to  rely   too   much   on   the   “agonistic”   side   of   the   problem.   Under   free   institutions   the   individual   ways   of   life   are   countless   and,   due   to   the   nature   of   ethical   choices,   incommensurable.   Pluralism   in   fact   brings   up   moral   trade-­‐offs   that   cannot   be   solvable   merely   appealing   to   abstract  moral  theories.  Although  at  same  token  some  common  ground  should  be  required   once   we   have   stated   pluralism   (as   such)   as   a   normative   principle   for   us.   To   recognized   incommensurability   is   to   recognize   the   normative   priority   to   toleration   and   mutual   respect.   This  leads  us  to  my  final  point.  It  is  not  possible  to  state  moral  pluralism’s  truth,   i.  

 

e.   to   recognize   its   objective   truth,   without   some   egalitarian   metric   concerning   mutual                                                                                                                           23

   I  am  thinking,  for  example,  in  the  kind  of  construction  proposed  by  Thomas  Scanlon  (1975;  2003).  

18    

19     respect  or  toleration.  Some  theories  as  the  neo-­‐hobbesian  accounts  of  liberalism  try  to  do   that  through  a  subjectivist  standard:  any  preference  or  desire  counts  and  pluralism,  as  was   already   said,   is   a   second-­‐best   equilibrium.   Even   for   this   kind   of   theory   liberty   is   not   enough  to  support  toleration.  Personally,  I  intend  to  favor  another  form  o  liberal  thought.   One  thought  in  which  toleration,  as  a  condition  to  political  legitimacy,  rests  on  egalitarian   bases24.  It  is  true  that  this  egalitarian  foundations  shall  bind  up  the  scope  of  acceptable  or   reasonable   arrange   of   values.   But   at   same   time   it   has   the   moral   strength   to   assure   the   distinction,  proposed  by  Thomas  Nagel,  between  personal  ethical  truths,  on  one  side,  and   public   justifiability   on   the   other   (Nagel   1987).   If   every   citizen   should   conceive   itself   as   a   free  and  equal  individual  they   can  treat  each  other  as  moral  persons  able  to  offer  (public)   reasons  for  their  actions.  This  is  my  interpretation  of  what  John  Rawls  has  called  the  moral   “duty  of  civility”  embedded  in  the  ideal  of  tolerance25.          

Works  of  Isaiah  Berlin:     LT:   “Logical  Translation”,  in:   Concepts  and  Categorie:  Philosophical  Essays.  Oxford  Press   1978.   PT:  “Does  Political  Theory  Still  Exist?”,  in:   Concepts  and  Categories:  Philosophical  Essays.   Oxford  Press  1978.   DUIW :   “The   Decline   of   Utopian   Ideas   in   the   West”,   in   The   Crooked   Timber   of   Mankind:  

Chapters  in  The  History  of  Ideas.  New  York:  Vintage  Books  1992   TCL  :  “Two  Concepts  of  Liberty”,  in:  The  Proper  Study  of  Mankind:  an  Anthology  of  Essays.   New  York:  Farrar,  Straus  and  Giroux  1997.     PI:   “The   Pursuit   of   the   Ideal”,   in:   The   Proper   Study   of   Mankind:   an   Anthology   of   Essays.   New  York:  Farrar,  Straus  and  Giroux  1997.    

Bibliography:     DWORKIN;  R.  1976  Taking  Rights  Seriously.  Cambridge  Mass.:  Harvard  Press.                  .  2006  “Moral  Pluralism”,  in  Justice  in  Robes,  Cambridge  Mass.:  Harvard  Press.  

                                                                                                                         

24

 This  is  in  my  view  how  John  Rawls  has  tried  to  settle  the  question  in  Political  Liberalism.      See  for  example  Rawls  interpretation  of  public  reason  as  an  “ideal  of  democratic  citizenship”,  (2005)   pp.  216-­‐220.     25

19    

20     GRAY;   J.   1993(a)   “Berlin’s   Agonistic   Pluralism”,   in:   Post-­‐Liberalism:   Studies   in   Political  

Thought,  London:  Routledge.                  .   1993(b)   “What   is   Dead   and   What   is   Living   in   Liberalism?”,   in:   Post-­‐Liberalism:   Studies  in  Political  Thought,  London  Routledge.                .   1995   “Agonistic   Liberalism”,   in:   Enlightenment’s   Wake:   Politics   and   Culture   at   the  

Close  of  the  Modern  Age    London:  Routledge  Press  pp.  65  –  87.   HOBBES;   T.   [1651]   1996   Leviathan,   TUCK;   R.   (ed.)   Cambridge   Texts   in   the   History   of   Political  Thought.  Cambridge:  Cambridge  Press.     KOLAKOWSKI;   L.   1981   “The   Death   of   Utopia   Reconsidered”,   in:   The   Tanner   Lectures   on  

Human  Values  pp.  229-­‐247.   KUHN;  T.  2003  O  Caminho  desde  A  Estrutura,  São  Paulo:  Ed.  UNESP.   LEBRUN;   G.   [1984]   2001   O   que   é   Poder?   São   Paulo:   Ed.   Brasiliense.   Coleção   Primeiros   Passos.       MACKIE,  J.  L.  1977  Ethics:  Inventing  Right  and  Wrong  London:  Penguin  Books.   NAGEL;  T.  1979    “The  Limits  of  Objectivity”,  The  Tanner  Lectures  on  Human  Values.                  .   1987   “Moral   conflict   and   Political   Legitimacy”   in:   Philosophy   and   Public   Affair,   vol.   16,  n.  3.  pp.  215-­‐240.     RAWLS,  J.    2005  Political  Liberalism  (expanded  edition),  New  York:  Columbia  Press.   RORTY;  R.  1983  “Postmodernist  Bourgeois  Liberalism”,  in:   The  Journal  of  Philosophy    vol.   80,  n.  10.                  .   1991   “The   Priority   of   Democracy   over   Philosophy”,   in:   RORTY,   R.   Objectivity,  

Relativism  and  Truth:  Philosophical  Papers  ,    Cambridge:  Cambridge  Press.     SHKLAR;   J.   2004   “The   liberalism   of   Fear”,   in:   YOUNG;   S.   P.   (ed.)   Political   Liberalism:  

variations  on  a  theme.  Albany:  State  University  of  New  York  Press  pp.  149-­‐166.   SCANLON;  T.  1975  “Preferences  and  Urgency”,  in:   The  Journal  of  Philosophy,  vol.  72,  n.  19,   pp.  655-­‐669.    

20    

21                  .  1992  “The  Aims  and  Authority  of  Moral  Theory”,  in:   Oxford  Journal  of  Legal  Studies,   vol.  12,  n.  1,  pp.  1-­‐  23.                  .  2003  “Contractualism  and  Utilitarianism”,  in:  SCANLON,  T.  The  Difficulty  of  Tolerance,   Cambridge:  Cambridge  Press.   TAYLOR;  C.  1985  “Interpretation  and  the  sciences  of  man”,  in:   Philosophy  and  the  Human  

Sciences:  philosophical  papers  II  Cambridge:  Cambridge  Press,  pp.  15-­‐57.     WALDRON;   J.   1987   “Theoretical   Foundations   of   Liberalism”,   in:   The   Philosophical  

Quarterly  vol.  37,  n.  147,  pp.  127-­‐150.   WALZER;  M.  1981  “Philosophy  and  Democracy”,  in:   Political  Theory    vol.  9  n.  3.  pp.  379-­‐ 399.              .   1983   “Spheres   of   justice:   An   exchange”,   in:   The   New   York   Review   of   Books,   21   de   Julho.              .  1985  Interpretation  and  Social  Criticism,  in:  The  Tanner  Lecture  of  Human  Values.   WILLIAMS;   B.   1982   “The   Truth   in   Relativism”,   in:   MEILAND   &   KRAUSZ   (ed.)   Relativism:  

Cognitive  and  Moral,  Notre  Dame:  Notre  Dame  Press.                  .  1985  Ethics  and  the  Limits  of  Philosophy  Abingdon:  Routledge  Press.                  .  [1996]  2009  “Tolerância:  uma  questão  moral  ou  política?”,  in:   Novos  Estudos  Cebrap   84  pp.  47–58.                  

21    

Smile Life

When life gives you a hundred reasons to cry, show life that you have a thousand reasons to smile

Get in touch

© Copyright 2015 - 2024 PDFFOX.COM - All rights reserved.