Politics, Property, Personhood: Kant's Rousseauian Return 1 [PDF]

Nov 28, 2011 - Politics, Property, Personhood: Kant's Rousseauian Return. Abstract: In discussing Kant's claim that the

3 downloads 5 Views 220KB Size

Recommend Stories


business personal property tax return
The beauty of a living thing is not the atoms that go into it, but the way those atoms are put together.

Politics 1
If you feel beautiful, then you are. Even if you don't, you still are. Terri Guillemets

2018 Form 1 - Annual Report and Personal Property Tax Return
Do not seek to follow in the footsteps of the wise. Seek what they sought. Matsuo Basho

Kants etik och dygdetik
Forget safety. Live where you fear to live. Destroy your reputation. Be notorious. Rumi

property tax return, punjab – self assessment form
Ask yourself: What vulnerabilities am I afraid to share with others who love me? Next

Corporate personhood as inhuman
You're not going to master the rest of your life in one day. Just relax. Master the day. Than just keep

Sovereignty and the Politics of Property
You have to expect things of yourself before you can do them. Michael Jordan

[PDF] Return to Life
Love only grows by sharing. You can only have more for yourself by giving it away to others. Brian

1 Intellectual Property education
I cannot do all the good that the world needs, but the world needs all the good that I can do. Jana

PdF Rental Property Investing
Love only grows by sharing. You can only have more for yourself by giving it away to others. Brian

Idea Transcript


Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

Politics, Property, Personhood: Kant’s Rousseauian Return Abstract: In discussing Kant’s claim that the state of nature is provisional or defective, such that moral agents stand under a duty to exit it, recent interpretive approaches to the Doctrine of Right have vacillated between what I call the theses of weak and strong provisionality. Weak provisionality holds that in Kant’s state of nature the norms of justice are in place. In the absence of an institutional enforcement mechanism, however, agents lack appropriate motivations to obey these norms. By contrast, strong provisionality holds that Kant’s view is that in the absence of a state the meaning and content of property rights, a crucial class of moral norms that pertains to the purposive character of human agency, remains completely indeterminate. In other words, agents in the state of nature have no grounds to conclude that these represent genuinely binding norms of reason as opposed to unilateral exercises of power masquerading as respect for freedom and autonomy. Based on an original reading of Kant’s remarks on the failure to secure property rights in the state of nature, I suggest that he holds a version of the strong provisionality thesis hitherto unrecognized even by its defenders. Kant’s view is that prior to the institution of a just state, the making of moral claims represents a form of moral self-deceit. Thus part of the task of becoming a moral person is learning to doubt the validity of moral claims made in the absence of a democratic political structure. If my interpretation is correct, Kant holds that to be a fully developed moral person is a political achievement. Kant’s ostensibly liberal and Lockean attempt to justify the state on the grounds that it protects natural (i.e., pre-political) rights thus ends up at the door of both Rousseau’s and Hegel’s thoroughly political conception of moral personhood as grounded in the achievement of legal reciprocity.

1. Introduction 1.1 Right, Ethics, and Kant’s Provisionality Claim The recent resurgence of scholarly interest in Kant’s political philosophy has focused on the complex relation between political and moral obligation in the Doctrine of Right (DR), part I of Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals (MM), by inquiring into the conceptual relations between two principles of practical reason: (1) the Universal Principle of Right (UPR) and (2) the Categorical Imperative as the supreme principle of morality (CI). UPR states, “Any action is right if it can coexist with everyone’s freedom in accordance with a universal law, or if on its maxim the freedom of choice of each can coexist with everyone’s freedom in accordance with a universal law” (6:230).1 It

1

Immanuel Kant, The Doctrine of Right, Part I of the Metaphysics of Morals, trans. and ed. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996). All references to Kant’s texts are to the Prussian Academy pagination appearing in the margins.

1

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

concerns the way in which an agent’s actions affect the capacity for the free choice of others. By contrast, the more familiar CI concerns maxims (very roughly, the reasons for action) that an agent can will to be a universal law.2 Governing the domain of right (Recht), UPR pertains to the form of interaction between agents, i.e., to the way in which the actions of one agent restrict the possible actions of another. It enjoins rules of legitimate coercion that render the free exercise of agency of one agent compatible with the agency of all. Governing the domain of ethics, CI pertains to the relation of a rational will to itself, surmounting its inclinations so as to act solely from the rational incentive of duty.3 It thus provides an internally prescriptive rule grounded in the autonomy of the subject rather than on an external coercive structure. Developing the insight that UPR pertains simply to what an agent does, whereas CI pertains to the reasons for which an agent acts, one recent strand of interpretation insists that the domains of interaction which each of these two principles govern represent independent and irreducible expressions of human autonomy, such that the “realm of right…does not form a part of morality (as defined by the categorical imperative) at all.”4 This view cuts against almost all the commentary on the DR, which

2

In its best-known formulation (the Formula of Universal Law), CI states, “[A]ct only in accordance with that maxim through which you can at the same time will that it become a universal law.” Kant, Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (4:421) in Practical Philosophy, trans. and ed. Mary Gregor (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996). See also MM (6:226). 3

For an account of the dyadic structure of right verses the monadic structure of ethics see Katrin Flikschuh, “Reason, Right, and Revolution: Kant and Locke,” Philosophy and Public Affairs, vol. 36, no. 4 (2008): 386 and Kant and Modern Political Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000), p. 101. For general and far-reaching speculations on the import of this distinction for ethical theory see Michael Thompson, “What is it to Wrong Someone? A Puzzle about Justice,” in Reason and Value: Themes from the Moral Philosophy of Joseph Raz, eds. R. Jay Wallace, Philip Pettit, Samuel Scheffler, and Michael Smith (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006), pp. 333-384. 4

Marcus Willaschek, “Why the Doctrine of Right does not belong in the Metaphysics of Morals, Jahrbuch für Recht und Ethik, 5 (1997): 205. See also Allen Wood, “The Final Form of Kant’s Practical Philosophy,” in Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals: Interpretive Essays, ed. Mark Timmons (Oxford: Oxford 2

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

at least in the Anglophone tradition begins with Mary Gregor’s claim, announced in the subtitle of her pioneering monograph, that in DR Kant “applies” CI to the domain of the political.5 As with many philosophically fruitful interpretive debates, understanding the relation between right and ethics cannot be settled simply by citing sections of DR. Certain passages clearly indicate that Kant understands principles of right to be derived from principles of morality, such that political obligations are a subset of moral obligations. For instance Kant writes, In contrast to laws of nature…laws of freedom are called moral laws. As directed merely to external actions and their conformity to law they are called juridical duties; but if they also require that they (the laws) themselves be the determining grounds of actions, they are ethical laws… (6:220). On the other hand, other passages insist that principles of right refer only to external standards for legitimate coercion. If this is so, then in the words of one commentator, “they cannot prescribe, command, or require that their addressees act in accordance with that standard.”6 For example, Kant writes that the law of right “lays an obligation on me, but it does not expect, far less demand, that I myself should limit my freedom to those conditions just for the sake of this obligation” (6:231). But if laws of right do not directly prescribe the reasons for which actions ought to be done, it is hard to see how they might be derived from principles of morality. Further textual evidence in favor of the separation University Press, 2002), pp. 1-21 and Marcus Willaschek, “Which Imperatives for Right? On the NonPrescriptive Character of Juridical Laws in Kant’s Metaphysics of Morals,” in Timmons, pp. 65-87. 5

Mary Gregor, Laws of Freedom: A Study of Kant’s Method of Applying the Categorical Imperative in the Metaphysik der Sitten (Oxford: Blackwell, 1963). For one of the most sophisticated recent defenses of the derivation of principles of right from morality (but not from CI specifically), see Paul Guyer, “Kant’s Deductions of the Principles of Right,” in Timmons, pp. 23-64. 6

Willashek, “Which Imperatives for Right?,” p. 71 (emphases in original).

3

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

of right from ethics can be found in Kant’s claim that the principle of right is analytic (which would seem to indicate that it does not stand in need of derivation from a synthetic principle such as CI) and that the Universal Law of Right is a “postulate incapable of further proof” (6:231).7 Attempts to square these claims have moved between high-altitude interpretive debates concerning the aims of Kant’s moral philosophy as a whole—for instance, whether Kant thinks that moral agency is always possible come what may or whether it depends on formal political protections, and so on some sort of priority of right with respect to ethics—and increasingly technical debates concerning issues such as whether or not the putative analyticity of a proposition such as UPR precludes the necessity for justifying it in relation to a synthetic principle, and the relation between postulates and principles in Kant’s political philosophy as opposed to his philosophy of mathematics.8 Yet despite its philosophical sophistication, much of this commentary remains at an interpretive impasse. In DR Kant seems both to insist that principles of right in some way follow from principles of morality, while also denying to principles of right the very features that are the hallmark of moral principles (e.g., the concern with intentions or reasons for action and not simply with the external form of what an agent has done, and the attendant location of normative authority in internal self-legislation as opposed to external coercion). The seeming irreconcilability of these claims may well stem from two

7

E.g., Wood, “The Final Form of Kant’s Practical Philosophy,” p. 7. For a helpful overview of passages supporting the Wood and Willashek reading, see Robert Pippin, “Mine and Thine? The Kantian State,” pp. 419-428, in The Cambridge Companion to Kant and Modern Philosophy, ed. Paul Guyer (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006). 8

On the technical matters see especially Guyer, “Kant’s Deductions of the Principles of Right.” For discussion of the possibility that a genuinely moral life depends on the just state, and so on the results of DR, see Pippin, “Dividing and Deriving in Kant’s Rechtslehre,” in Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Rechtslehre, ed. Otfried Höffe (Berlin: Akademie Verlag, 1999), p. 74. 4

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

higher-order commitments that structure Kant’s political philosophy. With the liberal tradition, Kant insists that extending the coercive power of the state to inner intentions violates individual freedom by turning the state into a kind of moral watchman. For Kant, as for Locke and Hobbes before him, the state must concern itself with actions and not intentions, legality and not morality (6:225). Thus, the state may legitimately imprison its subjects for failing to make good on certain kinds of contractual arrangements, but it cannot, most moderns are liable to think, punish its subjects because they have failed to adhere to these arrangements for the right sorts of motivating reasons (e.g., ‘because this is what duty commands’ or ‘because the laws must be loved for their own sake’) (6:220). Yet at the same time, Kant wants to argue that agents have a genuinely moral, as opposed to merely prudential, reason for endorsing the liberal democratic state as a coercive arrangement. Somewhat paradoxically, Kantian agents thus appear to have a morally weighty reason to endorse a morally non-committal state. On the working assumption that at least some of the apparent contradictions of DR may stem from tensions between these broader political commitments, in this paper I approach the relation between right and morality in a manner that has less to do with the relation between the specialized apparatus of DR and the larger architectonic of Kant’s moral thought, and more to do with the relation between his political theory and the social contract tradition with which he was in dialogue. As I will allude to throughout, I am particularly concerned to chart Kant’s oscillation between Lockean and Rousseauian commitments. More specifically, I propose to examine Kant’s argument for the duty to exit the state of nature, and his related claim that in the state of nature the norms of property, a crucial class of moral norms that pertains to the purposive character of human

5

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

agency, remain in some way provisional or not fully actualized, such that agents stand under a duty to institute a coercive structure in which the possession of property is consonant with the freedom of all. In what follows I will refer to both the duty to exit the state of nature and to the instability of property rights in the state of nature under the umbrella term, ‘Kant’s provisionality claim.’

1.2 Weak and Strong Provisionality Unfortunately, unlike interpretive debates concerning the relation between UPR and CI, on the subject of Kant’s provisionality thesis commentators often seem unaware that there is no significant scholarly consensus as to its precise meaning. Surveying the commentary, one notices an unthematized distinction between what I characterize as the interpretive theses of weak and strong provisionality. Weak provisionality holds that in Kant’s state of nature the norms of justice are in place, in the sense that what they enjoin is intelligible for moral agents. In the absence of an institutional enforcement mechanism, however, agents lack the appropriate motivations to obey these norms. By assuring each agent that other agents will respect these norms, the state simply renders more determinate the “definitive shape of these rights.”9 By contrast, strong provisionality holds that Kant’s view is that in the absence of a state the meaning and content of property rights remains completely indeterminate. In other words, agents in the state of nature have no grounds to conclude that these represent

9

Japa Pallikkathayil, “Deriving Morality from Politics: Rethinking the Formula of Humanity,” Ethics, vol. 121, no. 1 (October 2010): 130, 140.

6

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

genuinely binding norms of reason as opposed to unilateral exercises of power masquerading as respect for freedom and autonomy.10 I would submit that what ultimately lies behind the weak and strong provisionality interpretations are larger commitments about the legacy of natural rights for contemporary liberalism. But there are also local reasons for this divergence grounded in the conceptual structure of Kant’s argument. Throughout the course of DR, Kant offers three distinct but conceptually interrelated versions of the provisionality thesis. He argues that in the state of nature: (1) agents lack the appropriate assurance that others will uphold the duties of right and so lack rational motivations to do so themselves, (2) there is no definitive way to decisively delimit the boundaries between what is mine and what is yours, (3) there is no way for one agent to place another under an obligation consonant with the equal liberty of all. Following Ripstein, I call these the problems of (1) assurance, (3) indeterminacy, and (3) unilateral obligation.11 Kant has good reasons for making all three of these claims at different points in the text, not the least of which is that each instability in the state of nature grounds the

10

For strong provisionality see Flikschuh, “Reason, Right, and Revolution: Kant and Locke”: 383-84 and Arthur Ripstein, Force and Freedom: Kant’s Legal and Political Philosophy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2009), pp. 145-182. For some of the more far-reaching statements of strong provisionality see Pippin, “Dividing and Deriving in Kant’s Rechtslehre,” p. 78 and “Mine and Thine? The Kantian State,” pp. 438-439. 11

Ripstein, Force and Freedom, pp. 145-147 (and passim). Regarding (1) Kant writes, “I am therefore not under obligation to leave external objects belonging to others untouched unless everyone else provides me assurance that he will behave in accordance with the same principle with regard to what is mine” (6:255). Regarding (2) Kant writes, “The indeterminacy, with respect to quantity as well as quality, of the external object that can be acquired makes this problem (of the sole, original external acquisition) the hardest of all to solve” (6:266). There are numerous important passages on the subject of (3). To introduce a passage that I consider at length below: “When I declare (by word or deed), I will that something external is to be mine, I thereby declare that everyone else is under obligation to refrain from using that object of my choice, an obligation no one would have were it not for this act of mine to establish a right…Now, a unilateral will cannot serve as a coercive law for everyone with regard to possession that is external and therefore contingent, since that would infringe upon freedom in accordance with universal laws” (6:255-256).

7

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

necessity for different branches of government ((1) executive, (2) judicial, and (3) legislative). Furthermore, the problem of unilateral obligation pertains most obviously to the acquisition of property, while assurance and indeterminacy concern the protection of what one has already acquired.12 And all three instabilities are clearly related to one another. After all, if there is no way of drawing a secure boundary between what is mine and what is yours, agents do not stand under an obligation to uphold the duties of right, and thus they have no assurance that others will do so as well. Moreover, if declarations of property cannot even get off the ground, then drawing boundaries between what is mine and yours and establishing schemes to protect that boundary are activities that lack any moral sense (though they may serve a pragmatic function). Nevertheless, quite surprisingly many commentators have placed almost all the emphasis on (1) and (2) to the exclusion (3)—this despite the fact that (3) is obviously the most foundational. This leads them to adopt weak provisionality. Without (3), (1) and (2) give the impression that the norms of justice in the state of nature are intelligible, albeit unstable. By contrast, if one sees the main problem behind the provisionality claim as being (3), i.e., the very possibility that one agent could place another under an obligation at all, one tends to strong provisionality. On this construal of Kant’s state of nature, agents prior to the legitimate state have only the most tenuous hold on what it could even mean to enter into the practice of property obligations, since they have no grounds to

12

Again, Ripstein’s excellent analysis is responsible for introducing much needed order into these matters.

8

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

conclude that the very act of obligating another has any moral standing whatsoever.13 In the situation marked by (3) instability has given way to (near) unintelligibility. In what follows I reconstruct Kant’s provisionality argument in terms of a very strong species of strong provisionality. I argue that even those commentators who see the essential problem of the state of nature as one of unilateral obligation have not adequately accounted for why in the absence of a state it so much as appears to be morally problematic for one agent to place another under an obligation. Once we appreciate the scope and significance of Kant’s argument for provisionality, what emerges is the following quite striking position: making moral claims in the state of nature represents a form of moral self-deceit—a situation in which claims of right mask morally illegitimate self-preference. The only way out of this situation is to (re)constitute collective life as an order of practical reason (i.e., as a state), rather than as a relation of fields of antagonistic force relations devoid of an ordering principle of legitimacy. This, I submit, is Kant at his most Rousseauian.14 In later sections of this paper, I suggest that Kant pulls back from these Rousseauian results in ways that can be subjected to internal criticism.

2. Kant and the Political Actualization of Moral Personhood 2.1 From Locke to Rousseau 13

Although commentators who emphasize (1) and (2) to the expense of (3) tend to endorse weak rather than strong provisionality, they need not always do so. For example, in “Mine and Thine?” Pippin places emphasis on problems of assurance and yet ends up attributing strong provisionality to DR. 14

For the claim that Kant’s flirtation with the political status of moral freedom reveals his indebtedness to Rousseau, see Susan Shell, Kant and the Limits of Autonomy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2009), p. 237 and Pippin, “Mine and Thine?,” p. 438. In his analysis of DR, Terry Pinkard goes to the most Rousseauian extremes, arguing that DR reveals that for Kant orienting oneself in a self-determining harmonious unity is the only way to be truly autonomous in a meaningful, non-formal sense. See Pinkard, “Kant, Citizenship, and Freedom,” in Metaphysische Anfangsgründe der Rechtslehre, pp. 160-163. I suspect that this overstates Kant’s proximity to both Rousseau and Hegel.

9

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

The strong provisionality interpretation might appear to cut against the obvious fact that Kant is not entirely at odds with the tradition of natural right. Kant, like Locke before him, clearly constructs his state of nature as a state devoid only of law and distributive justice, not of moral entitlements more generally (6:306).15 This is why he countenances an innate (i.e., non-political) right to freedom. Kant writes, Freedom (independence from being constrained by another’s choice), insofar as it can coexist with the freedom of every other in accordance with a universal law, is the only original right belonging to every man by virtue of his humanity (6:238) (emphasis mine). The basic argumentative strategy behind the provisionality thesis is to show that the state of nature is unstable because in it the parties lack the means to effectively establish one of the necessary elements of the innate right to freedom: the right to acquire and conclusively establish claims to property. Kant reasons that if we have a moral right to freedom, we must also have a right to the necessary elements of freedom. (Or, more accurately, he reasons that one cannot disallow on putatively ‘moral’ grounds the necessary elements of moral freedom.) This is why parties in the state of nature stand under a duty to exit it, a duty to institute an order in which they can secure their moral entitlements to property. For Kant’s view that individuals stand under a moral duty to create the conditions for the exercise of their pre-political moral entitlements, consider the following passage: If no acquisition were cognized as rightful even in a provisional way prior to entering the civil condition, the civil condition itself would be impossible. For in terms of their form, laws concerning what is mine or 15

Cf. Flikschuh, “Reason, Right, and Revolution: Kant and Locke”: 382-389. Flikschuh argues that Kant has almost nothing in common with Locke because Kant’s state of nature is one in which we have natural rights but lack “morally valid claims to right” (383; emphasis in original). But as I show below, this is true only of claims to right involving human purposiveness (e.g., property rights), not of claims to right involving basic bodily integrity. Pace-Flikschuh, these are natural through and through. I address this further in 2.3 below.

10

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

yours in the state of nature contain the same thing that they prescribe in the civil condition…The difference is only that the civil condition provides the conditions under which these laws are put into effect (6:313).16 But as we will see below, despite Kant’s starting point in a Lockean world, he ends up with a Rousseauian picture of the strong dependence of moral personhood on political institutions.

2.2 The Natural Right to Freedom To see how Kant moves from the idea that we have a natural right to freedom to the claim that the state plays a necessary role in securing moral personhood, we must first go into a bit more detail about the meaning of “right” (Recht). An order of right stems from what Kant calls the “external” aspect of freedom, by which he means the way in which any individual exercise of freedom—understood as the discretionary capacity to set and pursue one’s own ends—necessarily affects the possibilities for the freedom of others (6:230). For instance, if I decide to sit in this particular chair at this particular time, I necessarily exclude you from freely determining yourself to sit in the same chair. In and of itself, this dimension of external freedom is not morally problematic. It simply follows from the fact that we are finite, purposive creatures, bound by space and time. Almost every kind of purposive activity—even standing quietly in one spot—restricts the possibilities of others. On the other hand, if the exercise of my external freedom takes the form of tying you to your chair, I necessarily restrict not just whatever particular end you might happen to have, for example, getting up and walking over to another chair, but your capacity to 16

See also 6:257.

11

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

set ends at all. This is a clear moral wrong, since it renders impossible your capacity to exercise your innate right to freedom. Now, one might be skeptical of drawing such a hard and fast distinction between any particular constellations of ends that an agent happens to have and her bare capacity to set ends at all, what Kant sometimes characterizes as the difference between the “matter” and the “form” of choice.17 But the moral import that one ought to draw from the distinction is intuitively obvious. It does not follow from considerations of external freedom—i.e., from the way that my actions necessarily shape your possibilities of acting—that I must always care about your particular ends. But it does follow that I must not act in a manner that restricts your capacity to choose anything at all (6:230). If freedom is genuinely a moral phenomenon, there must be a system of rules that ensures that the free self-determining capacities of one agent do not conflict with the possibility of free self-determination on the part of other agents. These rules constitute an order of right. Even though the Doctrine of Right is eventually going to have something to do with the role of politics, the most basic principle of right can be deduced purely from considering what must follow if external freedom is not to conflict with our moral entitlements. As we have seen, UPR states that “An action is right if it can coexist with everyone’s freedom in accordance with a universal law” (6:231). Despite those interpreters who argue for a strict separation between right and ethics, here Kant clearly brings in the familiar connection between morality and universality from his moral theory 17

For the language of “form” and “matter” with respect to choice see 6:230 and 6:246. Since this distinction is what in fact enables Kant to license vast inequalities in material wealth, it seems to me that querying the stability of the form/matter distinction is the direction that a properly Marxist (and so Aristotelian) critique of DR should take.

12

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

in order to establish that if we have a moral right to freedom, then we necessarily stand under a moral duty to exercise our external freedom in a way that is consistent with the external freedom of everyone else.18

2.3 “The Postulate of Practical Reason with Regard to Rights” I won’t give his arguments here, but from UPR Kant deduces two slightly more determinate sets of entitlements: (1) first, that we have a right to our own bodily integrity (6:248), and (2) second, that we have the right to forcibly hinder any attempt on the part of others to interfere with this basic right (6:231). In fact, from the bare possibility of moral freedom Kant deduces even more than this. Kant argues that it simply follows from the fact that I am morally free that I have the right to claim bits of the external world (i.e., bits of the world distinct from my own body) as falling under my discretionary purposes. Let us call such bits of the external world “objects.” This right to objects will turn out to be a right to property. Before getting to Kant’s argument for this claim, which he calls “the Postulate of Practical Reason with Regard to Rights” (6:246), it is important to keep in view its result. The Postulate establishes that part of what it means to respect each other as externally free agents is to respect each other’s claims to enduring discretionary use of objects. So the Postulate derives property from the entitlements of moral personhood.

18

Importantly, the force of this injunction does not stem from any particular relations of obligation incurred through the pair-wise interactions of discrete agents. Rather, it simply follows from every agents’ rational consciousness of the fact that a necessary part of being a moral person is being an externally free agent (6:232). So if it turns out that political interaction is necessary to genuinely secure the conditions for this basic aspect of moral self-consciousness—a striking claim that we will examine in more detail below— then the scope of politics will turn out to be a good deal more broad than the role it plays in securing interests that arise from narrower, more intuitively ‘political’ sorts of interaction (e.g., that you stay off my lawn).

13

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

Kant’s argument for the Postulate depends, first, on reflections concerning the conceptual structure of purposive activity. Some kinds of complex end-setting activity clearly involve the possibility of continual access to the particular material objects that are the means to one’s end.19 For instance, it seems hard to see how I could execute my end of building a chair if I’m continually preoccupied with protecting my dominion over the wood and my hammer. But reflections on the necessary role of possession in human end-setting activity are not sufficient to establish that such continual, unrestricted access to objects is necessarily rightful. Perhaps what is truly right is for us to share the hammer. (Though the fact that it seems unintelligible to suggest that we share the wood already tilts the argument in favor of at least some cases of unrestricted possession.)20 The claim that that some degree of unrestricted access to objects is closely tied to the dimension of human purposive activity that falls under the domain of external freedom is meant only to establish the prima facie plausibility of the rightfulness of such access. Let me explain further. Kant’s point is not that we necessarily have a right to exclusive use of bits of the external world because that’s the only way to be a purposive agent. To argue in this manner would be to admit considerations of human need (as opposed to considerations of human freedom) into the structure of right, in which case the rules of right would be heteronymous. Rather his point is as follows:

19

Kant implicitly tracks this point with his suggestion that to think of something as an object of my choice is to think of it as falling under my power (6:246). 20

Cf. Paul Guyer, “Kant’s Deductions of the Principles of Right,” p. 58 and Leslie Mulholland, Kant’s System of Rights, (New York: Columbia University Press, 1990), p. 275. Both Guyer and Mulholland claim that Kant has little to no argument for individual possession of property, and that whatever argument he does have depends heavily on assumptions about human nature that are not purely formal. See also Kenneth Westphal, “A Kantian Justification of Possession,” in Timmons (ed), pp. 96-99. 14

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

(1) The only way to be a purposive agent is to have unrestricted use of at least some objects. (2) The fact that we are purposive agents stems from our external freedom. (3) We’ve already seen that if an order of right is possible, there must be a way to square external freedom with our innate moral entitlements. (4) We thus have good reason to suppose that having exclusive access to objects is morally legitimate, or at least to search for such a legitimating principle. (5) If making claims to objects falls under the purview of external freedom, the only thing that could rule such access out of court is if it turns out to be incompatible with UPR (6:246-247).21 Kant will of course go on to show that making claims to enduring use of external objects, i.e., making claims to property, does not conflict with UPR. The Postulate is only the first step in Kant’s demonstration that we have a natural right to acquire something that extends beyond our right to our bodies. Given its preliminary character, the real importance of the Postulate lies in what it shows about what such a natural right must look like: having the right to something that extends beyond our right to our bodies entails having control over an object that lasts through time. In other words, the Postulate motivates the claim that if our entitlement to objects stems from the necessary role they play in enabling human purposive activity, as well as from the possibility that discretionary use of objects may enable purposive activity without infringing on the freedom of others, then I have a right to my hammer even when I lay it down over there, out of arm’s reach. And this necessarily entails that having something as my own is having a normative entitlement to it that extends beyond the empirical, physical fact of possession.

21

Kant’s argument toward the person who says, ‘Why isn’t it more rightful to share the hammer?’ is thus, ‘It’s only wrong for me to have exclusive use of the hammer if you can show me that such possession necessarily excludes the bare capacity for choice on the part of agents who don’t own the hammer. Either show me that’s the case, or stop whining about the dignity of sharing.’

15

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

From one point of view, Kant has established an impressive amount without bringing in the notion of a duty to leave the state of nature and institute the state. He has shown that we have rights to our own bodily integrity, which include the right to defend it, even with violent force. And he has established the possibility that we have the right to claim parts of the natural world as our own, where having something as your own is having a normative claim to it that persists through time and space. So it looks like prior to the exit from the state of nature, both the rights of bodily integrity and of property are fully intelligible, though perhaps unstable at the point of implementation. Thus, it might seem as though the thesis of weak provisionality accurately captures the argument of DR.

2.4 The Provisionality of the State of Nature But these results are actually quite bare. Although pre-political agents are morally entitled to possessions as a necessary element of their external freedom, it turns out that in the state of nature the right they have concerning these possessions comes to nothing more than the right to, quite literally, hold on to what they have (at this particular moment in time). In other words, it turns out that until we exit the state of nature my right to my apple is simply my right for you not to wrench the apple out of my hand while I hold it, which is not very different from my right to my own bodily integrity (6:250).22 In effect, Kant seems to be claiming both that we have and that we do not have property rights in the state of nature. As a preview to the interpretation I will develop in the rest of this paper as to what Kant could possibly mean by this, let me suggest that this situation of uncertainty stems 22

For more on the connection between rights to property and rights to my person see 6:262.

16

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

from the moral ambiguity surrounding cases in which one agent’s claim to property is challenged by another. The uncertainty can be described as follows: Using the kind of reasoning reflected in the Postulate, agents deduce that being externally free mandates rights to possession of an object as distinct from possession of oneself. They thus assume that they can have lasting discretionary use of the object, i.e., a normative entitlement to it. They think the apple is theirs even after they set it down. But then another agent comes along and swoops up the apple. Obviously, the ‘owner’ of the apple might struggle with the ‘thief.’ But doing so is morally ambiguous. It turns out to be not so clear that forcing you to return to me the apple that I earlier set down is in fact morally permissible. But if my actions aimed at re-securing possession cannot be rendered morally unambiguous, then what I thought was my right to enduring, real possession of my apple turns out to be nothing more than the right to have it while I hold it (6:261). Later I will return to this idea of moral ambiguity—the press of competing and antagonistic claims regarding moral entitlement—since it is in fact the key to seeing why the problem of unilateral obligation should lead us to attribute to Kant a very strong variant of the strong provisionality thesis. It is important to appreciate that if Kant’s state of nature were meant as an empirical description of what life would be like without a political order, it would be much easier to see what he could have in mind in claiming that my rights to property are provisional in this way. The claim would simply be that in the state of nature an agent cannot actually enforce his property rights because others are likely to ignore them, the result of which is that these rights are merely formal, empty. But since Kant’s description of the state of nature is concerned with right and not fact, we have to understand him as

17

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

saying something more like, ‘In the state of nature I morally have a right that I turn out not to morally have.’ Or, ‘I have a morally required right but lack the (moral) powers to effectively secure such a right, and thus I don’t actually have the right at all.’23

2.5 The Immorality of Property Claims? The Problem of Unilateral Obligation We now have enough on the table to see why the provisionality claim is so obscure. I think the best way to appreciate what is incomplete in the state of nature, and so the best way to appreciate Kant’s political solution to the problem of securing rights to property, is to more clearly state the apparent problem. We need to see what appears to be morally ambiguous about property rights in the state of nature in order to understand why exiting the state of nature dissolves the ambiguity. As we have seen above, the deepest instability in the state of nature concerns the problem of unilateral obligation. On this Kant writes, When I declare (by word or deed), I will that something external is mine, I thereby declare that everyone else is under obligation to refrain from using that object of my choice, an obligation no one would have were it not for this act of mine to establish a right (6:255). When an individual declares ‘this is mine,’ he permanently restricts the possibilities of others such that they can no longer rightfully use that bit of the external world. The question is why exactly the right of an individual to the permanent restriction of the possibilities of others cannot be fully secured unless we exit the state of nature and institute a political order. To appreciate the force of the provisionality thesis as it pertains to the problem of unilateral obligation, we would do well to consider the following intuition about the 23

Here I follow Arthur Ripstein’s helpful way of putting the problem in Force and Freedom, p. 147.

18

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

potential morality or immorality of property claims: It looks like the act of acquiring property is not quite as obviously morally wrong as tying you to your chair. But, on the other hand, it’s not quite as obviously morally acceptable as simply sitting in one of many chairs in the room. It is something more like stacking all (or at least a good many) of the chairs on top of one another and sitting on the pile. But, the intuition goes, how could my placing such definitive and permanent restrictions on your external freedom not count as simply enchaining you to the arbitrary dictates of my will, and so as a violation of your innate right to freedom? This problem will obviously arise in cases where I first acquire property, since in these cases I am seemingly just pointing to an object and declaring, ‘See that? That can never be yours.’ But as we’ve seen from the Postulate’s description of property as a normative entitlement, it also arises in any case where I assert a right to ‘what I’ve currently got’ that goes beyond my right not to have my body interfered with as I hold it.24 Both cases—the case of acquiring property, and the case of securing entitlement to one’s possessions—involve unilateral declarations of will (‘This is mine,’ ‘I’m going to take this,’ ‘Hey! You can’t touch that over there’) that arbitrarily restrict the freedom of others. But why exactly is this a problem?

2.6 Action-Restricting Action and Action-Restricting Obligation Here, our intuitions about chair-tying and chair-sitting cease to be a reliable philosophical guide. For, when pressed, they fail to account for why the act of declaring something as mine even appears to be morally wrong, and so to require the presence of 24

In trying to make sense of Kant’s murky text, it has been my guiding methodological conviction not to make too much of the distinction between securing access to one’s rightful possessions and initially acquiring such possessions, i.e., between holding on to what one has and actually getting something. Although Kant treats both of these dimensions separately, arguments from the section on property acquisition are key to making sense of Kant’s provisionality claim. 19

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

the state in order to secure its accordance with right. We don’t need to bring in the state to establish my right to sit in a chair, because its obvious that such an action is morally legitimate in that it involves no necessary restriction on the form of others’ agency (their capacity to set ends at all, rather than to pursue any particular end they might have). And we don’t need the state to establish that I can’t tie you to your chair, because it’s obvious that such an action violates your natural right to freedom. So why do we need to bring in the state to establish that I can in fact rightfully claim the chair as my property? As my earlier description of the moral ambiguity in the state of nature attempted to bring out, clearly it has something to do with how to proceed when my claim to property is challenged. On Kant’s view, any rational agent should unproblematically accept that your right to bodily integrity prohibits him from kicking the chair out from under you while you sit in it. But it is not obviously irrational for him to challenge that you have the right to stack all the chairs up (or, again, a good many of them) and claim them as your own.25 Perhaps he thinks, ‘No matter that I find something fishy about Kant’s distinction between the particular content of an agent’s ends and the general form of his capacity for end-setting at all, clearly forcing me to stand in the corner all day is a violation of my bare capacity to be an agent.’ Even before developing this case any further, it’s important to remark on the significance of the fact that contexts of this sort are in fact what lie in the background of Kant’s provisionality argument. This already indicates that for Kant the state is to be understood as a mechanism for securing moral content in the face of competing moral claims.

25

See 6:260-261 for Kant’s account of a normative challenge to property claims.

20

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

So Kant’s thought is that in the state of nature contestation over property looks to be legitimate, whereas an agent contesting that you have a right not to have the chair kicked out from underneath you is simply being unreasonable. But the question returns as to why. What is even potentially or possibly morally ambiguous about the right to claim a chair as my own? Here commentators unfortunately have followed Kant in not providing a clear enough answer to this question.26 Even Arthur Ripstein, on whose monumental recent study of Kant’s political philosophy I have depended at every turn, skirts this issue when he writes: The acquisition of property differs from other ways in which one person might be said to change the normative situation of another…[I]f I move from one place to another, I occupy space which is not available for your occupation while I am there. This change does not place you under a new obligation, but simply applies it to a different circumstance…The acquisition of property is different: in acquiring a piece of land I make it unavailable to you even when I am not occupying it.27 Or, “The original acquisition of property remains distinctive because it does not simply change the world: it places others under new obligations.”28 In these passages, Ripstein draws a distinction between the morally neutral (or at least, in accordance with right) way in which one’s actions necessarily affect the actions of others and the (potentially) morally impermissible way in which declarations of property constrain the basic endsetting capacities of another. Let us call this first kind of restriction action-restricting action and this second type action-restricting obligation. Ripstein’s argument hangs on the fact that action-restricting actions merely “change the world,” i.e., the context in

26

I thank Agnes Callard for pushing me to get clearer on this matter.

27

Ripstein, Force and Freedom, 151.

28

Force and Freedom, 153.

21

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

which an agent can act, whereas action-restricting obligations can look like they directly constrain others’ agential capacities and so constitute a violation of right. The problems with locating in this distinction an actual argument for the seeming impermissibility of property claims are two-fold: (1) First, Kant defines all rights as “moral capacities for putting others under obligations” (6:237) (emphasis mine). So even innate rights, rights that in no way depend on the state for their intelligibility, change the normative situation of others by placing them under new obligations. By appearing in your moral space, I place you under an obligation that you did not have before: the obligation to respect me as a moral person.29 Since Kant countenances a natural, non state-based right to freedom, from which the right to the respect of my moral personhood necessarily follows, there is nothing about the bare fact of placing another under an obligation that necessitates a turn to the state. Further, the sense in which my obligations to preserve your innate right to freedom existed before you appeared in my space, such that your arrival simply activates an obligation that was there anyway (Ripstein: “simply apply[ing] it to a different circumstance”), is the exact same as the sense in which due to the purposive character of human freedom I stood before your arrival under a not-yet fully specified obligation to let you have a measure of property. In both cases we must say that either the obligations were there anyway, waiting to be activated, or that once inside the scene of dyadic-interaction agents come to place one another under obligations that they did not have before.

29

A natural right does not depend on any actual act between agents (6:237), and so one might think that in this example the language of ‘placing’ another under an obligation finds no hold. But it is still the case that certain actions on my part activate your standing duties toward me. It is only my doing something—say, walking into your neighborhood—that sets off the constraint on your possibilities that was merely in potentiality when I stayed in my own backyard.

22

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

(2) Secondly, Ripstein does not adequately explain why restricting your possibilities by imposing an obligation on you is necessarily different from restricting your possibilities simply by acting in a non-obligation producing way. Both involve permanent restrictions on your agency. If I sit in a chair, I permanently restrict your possibility to kick it out from underneath me. If I make a claim to property, I permanently restrict your possibility of, say, vandalizing it, or perhaps more appropriately, simply using it for the reason that an essential element of your human purposiveness depends on it. (What remains of the wood in the forest is owned by you, and I desperately need it to make a chair.) So merely noting the difference between action-restricting obligation and action-restricting action won’t do the trick. Toward the end of the passage, Ripstein begins to acknowledge the relevant distinction when he writes that “in acquiring a piece of land I make it unavailable to you even when I am not occupying it” (emphasis mine). The salient difference between action-restricting obligation and action-restricting action thus lies in the kind of permanency they impose. By simply sitting in a chair my restriction on your possible actions is permanent only while I continue to occupy the chair. Whereas in claiming the chair as my property I make possibilities unavailable to you even when I no longer occupy the chair. So we might say that in the case of action-restricting action my present action permanently restricts your present possibilities, whereas in the case of actionrestricting obligation my present action permanently restricts your future possibilities.30

30

Kant never just comes out and says that this is his central worry about claims to property in the state of nature, though it can extracted from 6:263. In that passage he also discusses the further worry that in claims of property one subject appears to arbitrarily restrict the possibilities of all other agents. But given the concern of the UPR that the actions of any one agent be compatible the freedom of any other, I fail to see why the move from one agent to all agents could even appear to be morally salient to the parties in the natural state. 23

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

Kant’s intuition must be that what is potentially problematic about claims to property lies in the way in which they entail a permanent restriction of your future possibilities, whereas permanently restricting your present possibilities is simply a morally neutral fact about external freedom.31

2.7 Action-Restricting Obligation as a Threat to Agency Recall that in DR the only type of moral violation at issue are violations of the bare form of external freedom. So if Kant thinks that action-restricting obligation could even appear to be morally ambiguous in the state of nature it must be because stacking up the chairs and claiming them as my own looks to have at least something in common with the obviously immoral case of tying you to your chair, which violates your capacity to be an end-setter. But if this is in fact what he thinks, we are faced with yet another question, What is the relevant similarity between permanently restricting your future possibilities and interfering with your capacity to be an agent at all? To see why permanently restricting your future possibilities threatens to eviscerate your capacity to be an agent, consider the etiquette of chair sitting in the college classroom. For whatever deep reasons of group psychology, even students who haven’t had assigned seats since they were adolescents in elementary school tend to sit in the same seats session after session. And after a while, de facto claims to entitlement emerge. The chair in which I always sit becomes ‘my chair.’ Suppose a situation arises in

31

If this is in fact the point, then the reason that merely sitting in a chair is morally acceptable isn’t so much that it leaves open the possibility for you to sit in another chair, but that it’s assumed that someday I’ll get up, leaving my chair open to you. It is only a permanent restriction of your present possibilities. Conversely, if by standing in one spot quietly I am actually asserting that I’ll always be standing in this spot, that I’ll never ever move, then standing in one spot starts to look just as potentially morally problematic as making a claim to property. 24

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

which late in the semester one student sits down in the chair of another. The ‘rightful’ owner of the chair comes into class a bit late and says, “Hey you! That’s my chair.” To which our chair ‘thief’ replies, “I forgot my glasses today. This chair is so much closer to the board. My obligations as a student extend to taking good notes. So I think I’m entitled to sit in this chair.” To which the chair’s ‘owner’ replies, “Do a little bit of everyday anthropology. The implicit rules of the classroom stipulate that once you sit in a chair for long enough it’s yours. So that’s my chair. Get up!” This scenario brings out the way in which in situations of moral challenge one agent’s claims to the permanent restriction of another’s future possibilities for action begins to look morally problematic. If there is no principle that definitively secures my moral entitlement to the chair in which I habitually sit, it seems morally suspect that claiming it as mine could legitimately alter your world forever (or at least until the end of the semester). Such an act looks to at least potentially interfere with your agency in a way that extends beyond any one end you happen to have at any given moment. In Kant’s language, it threatens to infringe on the form as opposed to the matter of your choice.

2.8 An Omnilateral Will: Assurance and Indeterminacy Revisited One might of course contest this claim by conjuring up cases in which simple action-restricting action on the part of one agent has similarly drastic consequences for the agency of another. For example, if you and I exist in an extremely confined space, then by simply shifting my weight I may force you against the wall, rendering you unable

25

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

to move, breathe, or, indeed, set any ends at all.32 But such examples would be beside the point, because Kant’s claim is not that property is a violation of the external freedom of another, only that in the state of nature it would not be irrational for agents to take it to be. As it turns out, property claims are not morally problematic. They only appear to be because it is hard to see how a unilateral will could permanently restrict the future possibilities of other free wills. The grand conclusion of Kant’s argument for the duty to exit the state of nature is that such a restriction could be consistent with UPR only if the apparently unilateral declaration ‘this is mine’ were in fact the result of a prior, omnilateral will, an agreement of the free wills of all (6:259, 264). What kind of entity could have an omnilateral will? Obviously, only a legitimate state. Only the state can make possible both the rightful acquisition of property and the more conceptually basic right to possession that extends beyond the right to my person. By exercising an omnilateral will and so solving the problem of unilateral obligation, the state ensures that my claiming something as mine necessarily places me under an obligation to let you keep what is yours. This is the way in which the state solves the problem of assurance. And in the case of the acquisition of property, the state renders such an act rightful by ensuring that the same criteria apply to all. And so the state solves problems of indeterminacy. In sum, we stand under a duty to institute a state because our moral entitlement to property can be rendered compatible with the free agency of each if and only if such claims are secured and settled by the collective will of all.

32

Does this necessitate that my duty to respect your external freedom must necessarily take the form of standing perfectly still? For the impossibility of the shared exercise of external freedom under conditions of dire scarcity see Kenneth Westphal, “A Kantian Justification of Possession,” pp. 106-107.

26

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

2.9 Moral Self-Deceit Given the results of Kant’s provisionality argument, consider, as a bit of imagined phenomenology, what life in the state of nature looks like. Agents have the ability to reason themselves into accepting the legitimacy of property claims. But absent an omnilateral will they have no way of acting in a way that expresses this legitimacy. This has two major consequences for their acts of moral claim-making. First, there is a profound instability between what agents think they are doing as individuals and what they are actually doing as a matter of collective practice—there is a lack of fit between intention and actualization. Agents take themselves to be making moral claims, but absent adequate ground, they are simply asserting privilege. (“I have a right to this wood,” turns out to be nothing more than high-flown shorthand for, “I get to keep the wood and you don’t.”) Second, any agent’s attempt to defend his property from the encroachments of another is in no way different from a situation in which one agent illegitimately restrains another. What I take to be the defensive act of protecting my rights is nothing but an application of force. Kant expresses something like these points when he writes: It is true that the state of nature need not, just because it is natural, be a state of injustice (iniustus), of dealing with one another only in terms of the degree of force each has. But it would still be a state devoid of justice (status iustitia vacuus), in which when rights are in dispute (ius controversum), there would be no judge competent to render a verdict having rightful force (6:312). Contra Hobbes, in Kant’s state of nature agents may well have moral intentions. This is why it is not a “state of injustice.” But since there is no procedure by which such moral intentions can be translated into a rights-preserving reality, it is a “state devoid of justice.” In the absence of an appropriate institutionalization of morality, the inability to

27

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

make genuine judgments concerning right is not so much epistemic as it is structural. And so any actual instantiation of a rights claim must be without “rightful force.” Cast in this light, the argument for the duty to exit the state of nature turns out to be the claim that it is only by entering into a legitimate state that one’s claims to moral personhood can in fact represent anything other than clamoring for self-assertion. Thus, it is only by becoming a political person that one can be a moral person. If my interpretation is correct, then with the provisionality argument Kant is on the cusp of a view in which politics turns out to be necessary to avoid the idea that a single agent, operating solely on her own, could definitively arrive at the enormously complex demands of living together as free and equal members of a moral community. Or, said yet another way, by overcoming our natural tendency to moral self-deceit, the institution of a state as an order of practical reason retroactively reveals that pre-political claims to morality were always only partially actualizations of the real thing.

2.10 Having What I have and Being Who I am We should note just how far we have come from what one ordinarily thinks of as the de-politicized realm of Kantian morality. It has turned out that the only way to be morally free is to cede to the community the authority to (1) decide the conditions under which I can acquire an object, and (2) secure the conditions under which I can be said to be entitled to what I currently have. Although Kant does not go down this road—one that should have a familiar ring to students of post-Kantian idealism—we can extend his reasoning as follows: (3) my sense of what or who I am is clearly rooted in a sense of what I own or have. (4) So even my sense of myself seems to be intimately bound up

28

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

with a political network of norms that allow me to have what I have and so to be who I am. To put the point in slightly less psychological and so more recognizably Kantian terms, if having things other than myself (i.e., property) is key to being a purposive being, and if being a purposive being is a condition for being a moral being, and if I can only rightfully ‘have’ something other than myself if I exist in political community, then something extremely fundamental about what it means to be morally me depends upon the results of political agreement. My identity as a moral person is situated at a nexus of reciprocity between moral persons. Said yet another way, the constitution of a political order is what reveals that human purposiveness is congruous with moral personhood. In sum, Kant’s argument for the political status of moral personhood is as follows: (1) Being a moral person requires having property, but (2) in a pre-political condition making claims to property wrongs someone and so violates their claims to moral personhood. (3) But I can’t be a moral person in a way that violates the moral personhood of another, since it is a reciprocal concept. (4) So the only way to be a moral person is to be a political person.

2.11 Politics and the Dignity of the Moral Person As it stands, my last interpretive claim about the political status of moral personhood is still a bit obscure. Let me trace the way in which this idea emerges in Kant’s use of the terminology of the Roman jurist Ulpian to delineate the “General Division of Duties of Right.” Kant writes: (1) Be an honorable human being (honeste vive). Rightful honor (honestas iuridica) consists in asserting one’s worth as a human being in relation to

29

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

others, a duty expressed by the saying, “Do not make yourself a mere means for others but be at the same time an end for them.” This duty will be explained later as obligation from the right of humanity in your own person (Lex iusti). (2) Do not wrong anyone (neminem laede) even if, to avoid doing so, you should have to stop associating with others and shun all society (Lex iuridica). (3) (If you cannot help associating with others), enter into a society with them in which each can keep what is his (suum cuiquie tribue). […]Enter a condition in which what belongs to each can be secured to him against everyone else (Lex iusititaie) (6:236-237). Clearly Kant intends (3), the duty to enter into political society, to follow from (2), the general moral duty not to wrong.33The connection between (1) and (2), between being an honorable person and being a moral person, is similarly unsurprising. Some version of this claim pops up throughout Kant’s best-known works of moral theory. But (1) becomes especially relevant if one considers not the just the relation from (1) to (2) to (3), but the reverse dependence of (1) and (2) on (3). Kant thinks that although (3) follows from (2), we can only have a full and determinate sense of (2) once inside the sphere of (3). As we have seen, this is because prior to the legitimate state the morality of the state of nature is merely provisional and precarious. There is a similar relation of dependence and completion—in other words, dialectical dependence— between (1) and (2). But then there is no reason to think that the laws of transitivity do not hold. So (1) also depends on (3). In other words, if a political order is needed to secure moral relations, and moral relations are needed to secure the proper moral relation to oneself as possessing dignity or worth, then a political order is needed to secure one’s individual dignity. To put it in slogan form, ‘Moral dignity depends on political equality.’ We thus see quite clearly see that for Kant the connection between politics and moral

33

Once again, this should cast suspicion on interpretive approaches that argue for a strict separation between right and ethics. 30

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

personhood is not merely that politics secures the external realm of freedom, but also that politics secures internal aspects of my moral relation to myself, “the right of humanity in my own person” (emphasis mine). In the remaining sections of this paper I show that elsewhere in DR Kant backs off in various ways from these deeply Rousseauian and Hegelian insights as to the political and socially recognitive status of moral personhood.

3. Kant’s (Lockean Restrictions): Outline of a Critique 3.1 Right and Reciprocity It is worth repeating yet again that the provisionality of the state of nature is not a problem of collective action or prudence, but a genuine problem of morality. Kant’s claim is not that we need a state to imagine why prudentially rational agents would ever mark off pieces of land or refrain from trespassing on the land of others, but that we need a state to imagine how such activities could be morally acceptable. So when Kant details situations in which I have no reason to let you keep what’s yours if you won’t let me keep what’s mine, what he means is that in such cases I have no duty to let you keep what’s yours if you won’t let me keep what’s mine. But that would seem to be consistent with it being morally acceptable to let you keep what yours. Not having a duty not to X is compatible with one’s being allowed to X. At times Kant’s formulations do in fact suggest the relatively weak claim that I am not morally obligated to turn the other cheek. He writes, “No one is bound to refrain from encroaching on what another possesses if the other gives him no equal assurance that he will observe the same restraint towards him” (emphasis mine) (6:307).

31

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

And yet Kant countenances a genuine moral duty to exit the state of nature and institute a political order. And so, as I see it, Kant is actually committed to a much stronger view of the role of political reciprocity in morality. Kant ought to conclude that I actually have a duty not to let you keep what’s yours if you won’t let me keep what’s mine. Why? If I respect your property even while you usurp mine—if I look the other way while you creep on to my land by stealth of night and steal my apples—I am in effect placing my will under your discretion. And in allowing you to arbitrarily interfere with my external freedom I am directly attacking the system of right, which is what allows all of us, myself included, to be externally free in the sense of not bound by relations of dependence that violate our innate moral right to freedom. In relations of right there is thus no place for turning the other cheek, since the only thing that allows me to be a morally free person is the system of reciprocal limits that ensures that the freedom of one does not violate the freedom of another. Allowing you to interfere with my property should thus fall under the class of wrong operative in “willing to be and to remain in a condition that is not rightful” (6:307). Of course, it’s important not to get carried away here. My claim is not that Kant must necessarily accept that something like political fraternity, or dedication to the system of collective adjudication that establishes the freedom of all by determining the reciprocal boundaries of the freedom of each, has to be each individual’s primary mode of moral allegiance. To search for such a position in Kant would be to ignore that MM has two distinct parts, a doctrine of political right and a doctrine of moral virtue. Discussing this division, Kant clearly acknowledges that it can be a virtuous action to

32

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

keep up my end of the bargain even when you fail to keep yours (6:220). Kant’s reticence to countenance a duty not to let other agents infringe on one’s property stems from an understandable desire to render the Doctrine of Virtue compatible with DR. More importantly, as I mentioned in the introduction to this paper DR is concerned with what Kant calls external, juridical lawgiving. All of its arguments apply to a class of duties that an agent can count as following even if she is not acting from any sort of intrinsic, rational love for the duty per se. On Kant’s view, you can be a perfectly worthy moral subject if you obey the laws of the state for no other reason than that you don’t want to go to jail. From the fact that DR pertains only to external lawgiving one might conclude that all that Kant intends in linking moral personhood to the system of reciprocity is that I have a moral duty to participate in a legal structure that ensures the reciprocal rights of all, even if my ‘participation’ amounts only to simple legal obedience. On this view, I can be a subject both virtuous and politically upstanding if I turn the other cheek while you interfere with my lawn—the Doctrine of Virtue—just as long as I also support a system of laws that allows you to be punished for trespassing on the lawns of others (including my own)—the Doctrine of Right. But this seems difficult, if not impossible, to square with the claim that it is only through politics that agents can avoid moral self-deceit, only through a state that I can be sure that my enactments of moral virtue do not in fact represent an attempt to elevate my own desires to an unwarranted place of privilege.

33

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

3.2 Moral and Political Self-Deceit In his moral writings Kant is of course acutely interested in the pathologies of pseudo-moral self-regard.34 Kant’s insistence that the maxims on which an agent acts are never transparent to the agent herself registers the point that we can never actually know if we are doing the right thing for the right reason.35 And this lack of moral selfconsciousness is just what spurs us on to the moral task to try and try again. But unfortunately, Kant localizes such reflections to the moral sphere. As we have just seen, in the political sphere his official position is that intentions don’t matter, so that it is perfectly fine if agents advance claims of justice as a cover for their self-interest.36 This is the point behind Kant’s well-known defense of the liberal insulation of politics from morality: The problem of establishing a state…is soluble even for a nation of devils (if only they have understanding) and goes like this: ‘Given a multitude of rational beings all of whom need universal laws for their preservation but each of whom is inclined covertly to exempt himself from them, so to order this multitude and establish their constitution that, although in their private dispositions they strive against one another, these yet so check one another that in the public conduct the result is the same as if they had no such evil dispositions.’37

34

I owe this reminder to Erica Holberg’s criticisms of an earlier draft of this paper.

35

See for example Kant’s discussion of the human being’s fundamental inability to know the “purity of his moral intention” in the Doctrine of Virtue 6:392. See also Groundwork 4:404-405 and Critique of Practical Reason 5:29-32. 36

As Terry Pinkard points out, however, Kant’s notorious argument against a right of revolution depend, at least in part, on reflections concerning the tendency of political agents to mask self-assertion or lust for power as a concern for revolutionary transformation in the direction of justice. See Pinkard, “Kant, Citizenship, Freedom,” p. 169. 37

Kant, Toward Perpetual Peace, in Practical Philosophy 8:366.

34

Rafeeq Hasan

Draft 11/28/2011

Kant officially insists on an absolute separation between being a morally good human being and being a good citizen. Yet, as I hope to have shown, given the nature of the provisionality argument in DR, this distinction must break down.

35

Smile Life

When life gives you a hundred reasons to cry, show life that you have a thousand reasons to smile

Get in touch

© Copyright 2015 - 2024 PDFFOX.COM - All rights reserved.