Solutions to Semantics Problems [PDF]

Jun 1, 2010 - Squad helps dog bite victim. Ambiguous - like (d) but slightly more complicated. In one reading, dog bite

9 downloads 27 Views 37KB Size

Recommend Stories


Solutions to word problems
Ask yourself: When was the last time I said I love you to someone? Next

Static Solutions Solving Floor Care Problems (PDF)
This being human is a guest house. Every morning is a new arrival. A joy, a depression, a meanness,

Solutions to Problems Fundamentals of Condensed Matter Physics [PDF]
Solutions to Problems. Fundamentals of Condensed Matter Physics. Marvin L. Cohen. University of California, Berkeley. Steven G. Louie. University of California, Berkeley c Cambridge University Press 2016. 1 ...

Solutions to InClass Problems Week 14, Wed
Seek knowledge from cradle to the grave. Prophet Muhammad (Peace be upon him)

Solutions to Dynamic Facility Layout Problems
Ask yourself: If I could live anywhere in the world, where would I live? Next

Understanding calculus problems solutions and tips pdf
The only limits you see are the ones you impose on yourself. Dr. Wayne Dyer

The Overpopulation of Solutions to Philosophical Problems
Come let us be friends for once. Let us make life easy on us. Let us be loved ones and lovers. The earth

Spoon Feeding Solutions to Irodov Problems
If you want to become full, let yourself be empty. Lao Tzu

A Plastic Ocean Exploration Problems to Solutions
Ask yourself: What can I do today to live a better life tomorrow? Next

Solutions to selected problems in 5.6
Ask yourself: What is my life’s purpose? Am I acting accordingly? Next

Idea Transcript


Solutions - Semantics 1. For each of the following sentences, state whether it is ambiguous or not, and why. In particular, you should indicate what sort of ambiguity (if any) is present - word sense, syntactic structure, or a combination of the two. (Sentences c-f are supposed to have been actual newspaper headlines.) a. We saw her duck. Ambiguous - word sense and structural. duck could be a verb meaning to bob down, e.g. to avoid being hit, or a noun meaning an aquatic bird or a zero score in cricket or a kind of cloth, etc. Since the lexical categories of the two senses differ, structural as well as word sense ambiguity is present. The first version is: sees1(s1, agent[pro(w1, we1)], theme[duck1(agent[pro(h1, female1)])]) and the second is something like sees1(s1, agent[pro(w1, we1)], theme[the]) It is also ambiguous as to whether "we" all saw her duck on a single occasion, or whether different ones of "us" saw her duck on a range of occasions. I'd call this a kind of scoping ambiguity, similar to what you'd get with Every person saw her duck. There is further ambiguity in the word saw which could be the past tense form of see, or the present tense of the verb meaning to use the cutting tool called a saw. b. A man stopped at every truck stop. Ambiguous - was it the same man that stopped at every truck stop, or different men at at least some of the truck stops? a(m1 : man1(m1), every(t1 : truckstop1(t1), stopsat1(m1, t1))) or every(t1 : truckstop1(t1), a(m1 : man1(m1), stopsat1(m1, t1))) c. Killer sentenced to die for second time in 10 years. Ambiguous - structural - relating to attachment of the PP for the second time in 10 years. In one reading (the non-comical one) the PP attaches to sentenced - in the other reading the PP attaches to die. d. Teacher strikes idle kids. Ambiguous - the structure of the sentence depends on whether strikes is a plural noun meaning e.g. industrial action where the workers refuse to work (and the verb is idle) or strikes is a verb meaning "hit" (and idle is an adjective meaning something similar to "lazy"). e. Prostitutes appeal to Pope. Ambiguous - word-sense only. Appeal to can mean to seek assistance from or seem attractive to. f. Squad helps dog bite victim. Ambiguous - like (d) but slightly more complicated. In one reading, dog bite victim is an embedded sentence, in which the verb is bite, and this embedded sentence is the complement of the verb helps. In the other reading, dog bite victim is a compound noun phrase, with dog and bite functioning as qualifiers of victim, and the NP is the object/theme of helps. 2. Expand out the follwing ambiguous logical forms, giving a complete list of the full logical forms allowed by the ambiguous logical form: {run1 run2}(ev1, agent[pro(h1, he1)]) expands to run1(ev1, agent[pro(h1, he1)]) run2(ev1, agent[pro(h1, he1)]) sees1(s1, agent[pro(h1, he1)], theme[every]) expands to every(b1 : ball1(b1), sees1(s1, agent[pro(h1, he1)], theme[b1]) every(b1 : ball2(b1), sees1(s1, agent[pro(h1, he1)], theme[b1]) If really enthusiastic, you could expand the [ ], too, to get, e.g. every(b1 : ball1(b1), exists(s1, &(sees1(s1), agent(s1, pro(h1, he1)), theme(s1 b1)))). In the present tense, there is no further ambiguity. If past or future tense been present, there would have been a question as to the correct order of the quantifiers EVERY and EXISTS, corresponding to whether, for example, he saw every BALL1 (a spherical toy, say) at the same time - all together on a table, for example, or whether he saw different BALL1s on different occasions, say one BALL1 per day, until he had seen them all. gives1(gv1, agent[every], theme[a]) expands to either exists(gf1 : gift1(gf1), every(m1: man1(m1), gives1(gv1, m1, gf1))) or every(m1: man1(m1), exists(gf1 : gift1(gf1), gives1(gv1, m1, gf1))) The first of these says that there is a gift gf1 and all the men jointly give it to someone. The second one says that, in effect, each man gives his own separate gift. One could debate about the scope of the existentially quantified gv1 as in the preceding example, as well. not)(r1, agent[every]) expands to not(every(m1 : &(man1(m1), (happy m1)), run1(r1, agent[m1])) every(m1 : &(man1(m1) happy(m1)), not(run1(r1, agent[m1])) not(every(m1 : &(man1(m1) happy(m1)), run2(r1, agent[m1])) every(m1 : &(man1(m1) happy(m1)), not(run2(r1, agent[m1])) 3. Simplify the following formulae using lambda reduction: ( X, p(X)) a reduces to p(a). ( X, X(a)) ( Y, q(Y)) reduces first to ( Y, q(Y))(a) and then to q(a). ( X, (( Y, p(Y)) X))(a) reduces first to ( X, p(X))(a) and then to p(a). 4. Using the interpretation rules defined in Chapter 9 of Allen and shown in lectures, and defining any others that you need, give a detailed trace of the interpretation of the sentence The man gave the apple to Bert. In particular, give the analysis of each constituent and show its sem feature. Begin by listing the lexical entries for the words: apple, Bert, gave, man, the, to: apple n(sem(apple1), agr(3s)) Bert name(agr(3s), sem('Bert')) gave v(sem(give1), vform(past), subcat(np_pp:to), agr({3s, 3p})) man n(sem(man1), agr(3s)) man v(sem(man2), vform(base), subcat(np), agr(3s)) the art(sem(the), agr({3s 3p})) to p(pform(poss), sem(to-poss1)) We will also be using some of the semantically augmented grammar rules from Grammar 9.3 in Allen (reproduced in the lecture notes), and we have to invent two extra ones for np Õ name, pp Õ p np, and vp Õ v np pp:to. You could do this by analogy with e.g. the rule for vp Õ v pp in the lecture notes. 14. PP(pred(–), pform(?pf), sem(?semnp)) Õ P(pform(?pf) NP(sem(?semnp)) 15. VP(var(?v), sem(lambda(A4, ?semv(?v, A4, ?semnp, ?sempp)))) Õ V[_np_pp:to](sem(?semv)) NP(sem(?semnp)) PP(sem(?sempp)) In this rule, A4 is a variable holding a place for the subject, and the ?semnp is the direct object while the ?sempp is the pp for the indirect object. The word the is parsed as an article using the lexical lookup. Similarly man is parsed as a noun (and also as a verb, but this version leads nowhere, so we shall ignore it). Both words have var features generated for them, but that for the is never used. Let the var feature for man be m1. Grammar rule 7 then interprets the noun as a cnp (common noun phrase) and inherits the var feature of the noun. At this point we have det(sem(the1)) , n(sem(man1), var(m1)) and cnp(sem(man1), var(m1)). Grammar rule 6 combines the sems of the det and the cnp and the var of the cnp to build an np: np(sem(the1, var(m1)). Next the verb gave is looked up and gives rise to v(sem(past(give1)), var(ev1)). Then the words the and apple are in turn looked up, as were the and apple and give rise to (another) det(sem(the1)), an n(sem(apple1), var(a1)), a cnp(sem(apple1)), var(a1)), and an np(sem(the1(a1, apple1(a1)), var(a1)). The word to is looked up, giving a constituent p(sem(to-poss1)) (with an unused var feature). The word Bert is looked up, giving a constituent name(sem('Bert'), var(b1)). Rule 5 then interprets the name as an np, producing: np(sem(name(b1, 'Bert')), var(b1)). Rule 14 then combines this np with p(sem(to-poss1), pform(poss)) to produce pp(pred(–), pform(poss), sem(name(b1, 'Bert'))). Then rule 15 combines the V, the np(sem(the1(a1, apple1(a1)), var(a1)). and the PP to produce vp(var(ev1), sem(lambda(A4, past(give1)(ev1, A4, the1(a1, apple1(a1)), name(b1>, 'Bert'))))). Finally, rule 1 combines the np(sem(the1, var(m1)). with the VP to produce: s(sem(lambda(A4, past(give1)(ev1, A4, the1(a1, apple1(a1)), name(b1, 'Bert'))) the1(m1, man1(m1)) )) and the sem simplifies to past(give1)(ev1, the1(m1, man1(m1)), the1(a1, apple1(a1)), name(b1, 'Bert')) (The var feature of the whole sentence is ev1.) © Bill Wilson, 1996-2008. Last modified on Last modified 2 June 2010 CRICOS Provider Code No. 00098G

Smile Life

When life gives you a hundred reasons to cry, show life that you have a thousand reasons to smile

Get in touch

© Copyright 2015 - 2024 PDFFOX.COM - All rights reserved.